Log in

There is an epistemic problem in animal consciousness research

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Which non-human animals are phenomenally conscious? In this paper I argue that the distribution of phenomenal consciousness in the animal world is ultimately an unsolvable issue, because of an underlying problem inherent in the field: what I call the Kinda Hard Problem. The Kinda Hard Problem arises because the grounds on which we base our consciousness attributions to humans third-personally are either unavailable or ambiguous once we move to the animal case. Its nature is that of an epistemic problem: we cannot collect enough evidential grounds to justify attributions of phenomenal consciousness (and attributions of its lack) to non-human animals. Thus, it is impossible to ground rational belief one way or another regarding animal consciousness. This paper presents the problem and explains how it differs from other problems of consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Availability of data and materials: Not applicable.

Notes

  1. The distribution question has also been referred to as “the Who Problem” (Prinz, 2005) and “the other species of mind problem” (Allen and Bekoff, 1997).

  2. This point can be presented using counterfactuals. Laws of nature, grounding claims, and causal relations can be cashed out in terms of counterfactuals. The truth of a certain scientific theory (let’s say, Global Workspace theory) can be cashed out in terms of the truth of counterfactuals on what persons would have experienced under certain conditions. The fact I myself didn’t participate in the experiments supporting e.g. Global Workspace theory doesn’t undermine the theory, because a world where I was the subject in those experiments is close by. There is a truth-value to the counterfactual “if I were the subject in this experiment, I would have experienced such-and-so in these circumstances”. However, once we move to worlds that are far apart -that is, worlds were essential facts about my personal identity do no longer hold, worlds where I could be a mouse or a boar- the truth-value of the counterfactual is indeterminate.

  3. By animal, I mean the standard or representative individuals of the species.

  4. Abnormal cases (like cases of individuals in a vegetative state, comma, or who have non-standard nervous system composition) require a different treatment (see Shea & Bayne 2010 for discussion).

  5. I thank two anonymous reviewers for encouraging me to make this point explicit.

  6. Tools include (but are not limited to) behavioral experiments (like those using reaction times, eye tracking, psychophysical responses), brain imaging (like PET or fMRI), computational models or neurobiological methods like direct brain stimulation.

  7. I will be using “states” and “events” interchangeably; we don’t need to commit to whether states or events are the relevant ontological units.

  8. “Most often” because nothing prevents us, in principle, from having a cognitive scientific account of consciousness that presents non-physical qualia as partly constitutive of phenomenally conscious mental states.

  9. This seems a consequence of Human Consciousness, Nomological Character of Physical-Phenomenal Relations, and Phenomenal Realism.

  10. I use the term “combination” to be neutral of whether PSERTT1, PSERTT2 and the forth are specified as a conjunction or a disjunction. I will talk more about this on section 5.

  11. In this footnote, I will list some of the variations. What I say in sections 3 and 4 applies to all of these. Some of these variations can be combined.

    • Restricting the scope of [phenomenally conscious mental states]. On occasions, the Naturalistic Strategy is not run over phenomenal consciousness in general, but for a particular kind of experience (e.g. pain). In that case, there will also be an explicit mention of some external conditions (e.g. a limb being recently stubbed) that go into the PSERTTs. That would make the empirical finding of some of the PSERTTs in premise (ii) trivial (since we created the circumstances), but not others (i.e. those that are internal to the animal, and which we haven’t intervened upon).

    • Broadening the scope of [this animal]. Sometimes the Naturalistic Strategy is not run over particular specimens, but over a certain taxonomical category –e.g. individuals of a species, genus, family or order. This would change the formulation of (ii) and (C), but the structure of the argument remains the same.

    • Looking for reliable indicators of [the absence of conscious mental states]. Suppose that we find a chemical compound (say, a certain sedative) that in humans appears to trump phenomenally conscious states –i.e. the presence of this chemical compound is a reliable indicator, in humans, of the absence of phenomenally conscious states (note: there is nothing special about chemical compounds; maybe an inhibitive cognitive process can play the same role). We can reformulate (i) as: “PSERTTs (or a combination of PSERTT1, PSERTT2, PSERTT3…) are a reliable indicator of the absence of phenomenally conscious mental states, in humans”. We can reformulate (C) as: “the animal probably lacks phenomenally conscious mental states”. We can reformulate consideration (v) (not yet introduced in the main text) as: “we cannot know whether PSERTTs are reliable indicators for the lack of phenomenal consciousness in all creatures”. The structure of the argument, and the way the considerations run, remains unchanged.

    • Strengthening [the link] between PTs and consciousness. A physicalist might want to run the strategy by considering that PSERTTs are identical to, or are constitutive of, phenomenally conscious mental states. The Naturalistic Strategy for the identity claim can be reformulated as: (i) “PSERTTs (or a combination of PSERTT1, PSERTT2, PSERTT3…) are identical to phenomenally conscious mental states in humans”; (C) “this animal has phenomenally conscious mental states”. Since the PSERTTs the Naturalistic Strategy is about are those expressible in theoretical terms, the identity claim (i) might turn out to be false or only approximately accurate. Ditto for the whole thing, in the case of claims about constitutive relations.

    • Restricting the sorts of physical states that might go into [PSERTT]. For instance, a functionalist might want to emphasize that only functional roles can go on the PSERTT. The Naturalistic Strategy, as formulated in the main text, can accommodate this move without further changes.

    Two final remarks: this list is not exhaustive. (Also, any variations might face additional problems that threaten their inductive strength.) The point is that they would also face the Kinda Hard Problem.

  12. I thank an anonymous reviewer for the suggestion to incorporate Staley’s notion of secure evidence to the discussion.

  13. A reminder for the reader. (i) is: “PSERTTs (or a combination of PSERTT1, PSERTT2, PSERTT3…) are reliable indicators of phenomenally conscious mental states in humans”.

    (ii): “PSERTTs are also present in this animal (e.g. as found empirically)”.

  14. In footnote 10, I explain how the Naturalistic Strategy can be modified to accommodate to arguments defending the lack of consciousness in animals.

  15. For example, by adopting a “precautionary principle”, such that we extend protection to animals in the absence of certainty as to whether they feel pain (see Bradshaw 1998, Birch 2017).

  16. E.g., susceptibility to psychological harm or suffering; see Carruthers 1999, 2004.

References

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2020). The animal mind: An introduction to the philosophy of animal cognition. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K., & Beck, J. (Eds.). (2017). The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1956). The Problem of Knowledge. Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barron, A. B., & Klein, C. (2016). What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(18), 4900–4908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2017). Animal sentience and the precautionary principle. Animal Sentience, 2(16), 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2022). The search for invertebrate consciousness. Noûs, 56, 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2002). The harder problem of consciousness. The Journal of Philosophy, 99(8), 391–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5–6), 481–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradshaw, R. H. (1998). Consciousness in non-human animals: Adopting the precautionary principle. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5(1), 108–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (1999). Sympathy and subjectivity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77(4), 465–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal Consciousness: A naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2004). Suffering without subjectivity. Philosophical Studies, 121(2), 99–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2019). Human and animal minds: The consciousness questions laid to rest. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1997). Moving forward on the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(1), 3–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F., Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences, vol. 2, pp. 263–275. https://profiles.nlm.nih.gov/spotlight/sc/catalog/nlm:nlmuid-101584582X469-doc

  • Dehaene, S. (2014). Consciousness and the brain: Deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79(1–2), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, E., Sarter, M., & Lustig, C. (2008). Rats and humans paying attention: Cross-species task development for translational research. Neuropsychology, 22(6), 787–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. M. (2016). The ancient origins of consciousness: How the brain created experience. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feser, E. (2006). Philosophy of Mind: A Beginner’s Guide. Oneworld.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Other minds: The octopus, the sea, and the deep origins of consciousness. Farrar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2020). Metazoa: Animal minds and the birth of consciousness. UK: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S., Wang, L., McAlonan, K., Torres-Cruz, M., & Krauzlis, R. J. (2022). Stimulus-driven visual attention in mice. Journal of Vision, 22(1), 11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gosseries, O., Bruno, M. A., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Laureys, S., Schnakers, C. (2009). Consciousness in the locked-in syndrome. In S. Laureys and G. Tononi (eds.), The neurology of consciousness: Cognitive neuroscience and neuropathology (pp. 191–203). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-374168-4.00015-0

  • Graziano, M. S. (2019). Rethinking consciousness: a scientific theory of subjective experience. WW Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herculano-Houzel, S. (2009). The human brain in numbers: A linearly scaled-up primate brain. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 3, 31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyslop, A., & Jackson, F. C. (1972). The analogical inference to other minds. American Philosophical Quarterly, 9(2), 168–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyslop, Alec, “Other Minds,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Eds.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/other-minds/. Accessed 22 March 2019.

  • Jackendoff, R. (1987). Consciousness and the computational mind. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960077

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2011). Philosophy of mind. Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korbo, L., Pakkenberg, B., Ladefoged, O., Gundersen, H. J., Arlien-Søborg, P., & Pakkenberg, H. (1990). An efficient method for estimating the total number of neurons in rat brain cortex. Journal of Neuroscience Methods, 31(2), 93–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landman, R., Spekreijse, H., & Lamme, V. A. (2003). Large capacity storage of integrated objects before change blindness. Vision Research, 43(2), 149–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, H. C., & Passingham, R. E. (2006). Relative blindsight in normal observers and the neural correlate of visual consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(49), 18763–18768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubach, M., Amarante, L. M., Swanson, K., & White, S. R. (2018). What, If Anything, Is Rodent Prefrontal Cortex?. eNeuro, 5(5), ENEURO.0315-18.2018. https://doi.org/10.1523/ENEURO.0315-18.2018

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(October), 354–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. P. (2003). A naturalist–phenomenal realist response to block's harder problem. Philosophical Issues, 13, 163-204. https://doi.org/10.1111/1533-6077.00011

  • Macleod, M., & Mohan, S. (2019). Reproducibility and Rigor in Animal-Based Research. ILAR Journal, 60(1), 17–23. https://doi.org/10.1093/ilar/ilz015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michel, M. (2019). Fish and microchips: On fish pain and multiple realization. Philosophical Studies, 176(9), 2411–2428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat. Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 1, 159–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pargetter, R. (1984). The scientific inference to other minds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62(2), 158–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2012). The conscious brain. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2005). A neurofunctional theory of consciousness. In A. Brook and K. Akins (eds.) Cognition and the brain: Philosophy and neuroscience movement (pp. 381–96). New York: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610608

  • Rollin, N. (1989). The unheeded cry. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaeffer, D. J., Hori, Y., Gilbert, K. M., Gati, J. S., Menon, R. S., & Everling, S. (2020). Divergence of rodent and primate medial frontal cortex functional connectivity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 117(35), 21681–21689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K., Baars, B. J., & Edelman, D. B. (2005). Criteria for consciousness in humans and other mammals. Consciousness and Cognition, 14(1), 119–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation: A new ethics for the treatment of animals. Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 74(11), 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staley, K. W. (2004). Robust Evidence and Secure Evidence Claims*. Philosophy of Science, 71(4), 467–488. https://doi.org/10.1086/423748

  • Tye, M. (2016). Tense bees and shell-shocked crabs: Are animals conscious? Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voelkl, B., Altman, N. S., Forsman, A., Forstmeier, W., Gurevitch, J., Jaric, I., Karp, N. A., Kas, M. J., Schielzeth, H., van de Casteele, T., & Würbel, H. (2020). Reproducibility of animal research in light of biological variation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 21(7), 384–393. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41583-020-0313-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, U., Baker, L., & Rostron, C. (2014). Searching for inhibition of return in the rat using the covert orienting of attention task. Animal cognition, 17(5), 1121–1135. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-014-0745-0

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Peter Carruthers for his helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I am also indebted to an audience at the University of Maryland’s Philosophy Department work in progress, an audience at the Philosophy of Science Association’s 2018 meeting, and an audience at the American Philosophical Association’s 2022 Central meeting. Thanks as well to Eric Saidel, Amber Polk, Aiden Woodcock, Andew Knoll, Julius Schoenher, Chris Masciari, Shen Pan, Andrew Fyfe and Julia Janczur. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Funding

The author is grateful for a Fulbright-Spain fellowship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Single-authored.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aida Roige.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

None.

Additional information

Publisher's note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roige, A. There is an epistemic problem in animal consciousness research. Phenom Cogn Sci (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09912-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09912-3

Keywords

Navigation