Log in

A mechanistic guide to reductive physicalism

  • Paper in the Philosophy of the Sciences of Mind and Brain
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

Causal mediation mechanisms are well supported by available experimental evidence and provide a practicable way to reductive physicalism. According to the causal mediation account of mechanistic explanation, descriptions as diverse as ‘black-box’ phenomena, mechanistic sketches and schemas mixing physically interpreted and operationalized biological, psychological and social variables, and detailed descriptions of mechanisms refer to the same causal structure circumscribed within the spatiotemporal boundaries of a replicable experimental setup. The coreference of coarser- and finer-grained descriptions of causal structures opens new possibilities for testing the reductive physicalism conjecture. I discuss experimental designs supporting the causal mediation account and show how recent studies demonstrating the biological mediation of mind-mind causal processes can provide evidence for reductive physicalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a nonreductive proposal, see Krickel (2018).

  2. This explanatory standard corresponds to what Seth (2021, Ch. 1) calls the ‘real problem of consciousness,’ the goal of which is “to explain, predict, and control the phenomenological properties of conscious experience.”

  3. If (i)-(iii) are construed as necessary and sufficient conditions for mechanistic constitution, the trio defines the set of relationships in the world that simultaneously behave like material composition and reciprocal manipulability, where manipulability is causation as understood by interventionist accounts. Since the properties of composition and causation are mutually exclusive (e.g., one is synchronic, the other diachronic), their simultaneous conjunction stipulates a counterintuitive mode of existence analogous to the wave-particle duality. Following Craver and Bechtel (2007), the more intuitive interpretation adopted in this paper is that mechanistic constitution is a type of material composition, but not all material composition is mechanistic composition.

  4. In the above scenarios, there is no mechanistic constitution relationship behaving both like identity/composition and causality (manipulability). Instead, identity and composition relationships merely appear to be causal due to experimental artefacts.

  5. Rod (and cone) cells are ‘on’ in the dark (i.e., depolarized at -40 mV, corresponding to the ‘dark current’ discovered Hagins and coworkers) and ‘off’ when stimulated by light (hyperpolarized to a potential of -60mV, as indicated by Tomita). It was subsequently discovered that cGMP levels are high in the dark and keep cGMP-gated sodium channels open, hence the inward dark current resulting in the inhibitory neurotransmitter glutamate being released in the synaptic cleft. Light results in the activation of a phosphodiesterase, which hydrolyzes cGMP, reducing its the intracellular concentration. cGMP-gated sodium channels close, causing a hyperpolarization of the cell due to a continuous efflux of potassium ions. Hyperpolarization causes voltage-gated calcium channels to close and therefore of calcium levels in the cell to drop. This reduces the amount of inhibitory glutamate released in the synaptic cleft, causing the depolarization (excitation) of bipolar neurons (Fu, 2020). Note also that this explanation too is strictly about causal mediation, not mechanistic constitution.

  6. ‘Dark permeability’ refers to the inward Na+ dark current explained in note 5. Methylene ATP analogs are resistant to hydrolytic attack by nucleotide phosphohydrolases and are thought to act as competitive inhibitors of nucleotide cyclases.

  7. Mechanisms are described as causal pathways doesn’t entail that they are linear. For example, in the absence of measurements of intermediary stages, a cyclical metabolic pathway, such as Krebs’ cycle, appears as a linear input-output phenomenon (2 acetyl-CoA, 6 NAD+, 2 FAD, 2 ADP + Pi→ 4 CO2, 6 NADH, 6 H+, 2 FADH2, 2 ATP, 2 CoA).

  8. Some authors argue that the empirical justification of antireductionism rests primarily on the notion that causal inference from controlled experiments is indifferent to the nature of the variables manipulated in the experiment (Baetu, 2019b; Campbell, 2008; Kendler & Campbell, 2009; Woodward, 2008). For instance, if we agree that ibuprofen, a drug known to target the molecular mechanisms of inflammation, has a measurable analgesic effect on pain (as measured by verbal reports) because randomized controlled trials demonstrate a statistically significant difference in pain ratings between test patients exposed to ibuprofen and comparable control patients (Rainsford, 2011), then we must concede that hypnotic suggestion targeting expectations must also have a real analgesic effect, since methodologically equivalent randomized trials likewise demonstrate a statistically significant difference in reported pain between test patients exposed to hypnotic suggestion and comparable control patients (Rainville, 2008).

  9. The biopsychosocial consensus is also reflected in the IASP (2020) definition of pain.

  10. Haxby (2012, 853) explains the technique as follows: “The idea was straightforward and based on a concept from conventional statistics, namely split-sample cross-validation. If a given stimulus category evoked a distinct pattern of activity, then independent observations of the response to that category should be more similar to each other than to responses to different categories. Correlation of patterns was the chosen measure of similarity, and I made independent observations by dividing the data for each subject into two halves–even-numbered and odd-numbered runs. Thus, I predicted that within-category correlations would be higher than between-category correlations.”

  11. In the absence of experimental techniques selectively interfering with the activity of specific brain areas in humans, causal mediation was assessed by statistical methods. Psychological manipulations (conditioning individuals to associate auditory cues or options denoted by abstract symbols with high- and low-intensity noxious heat) were the independent variable, trial-by-trial pain ratings the dependent variable, and trial-by-trial SIIPS1 and NPS responses during pain were the mediating variables transmitting the influence of the independent variable to the dependent variable.

  12. Reference may hold true only locally–that is, only as far as pain modulating effects are concerned, without being generalizable to other experimental setups or phenomena involving measurements or manipulations of the variable expectation. If so, this would suggest that psychological function is underpinned by a variety of related or unrelated biological mechanisms [e.g. (Corns, 2012; Hardcastle, 1999)]. This is certainly true of many biological functions (e.g., gene expression regulation, immune responses, metabolic pathways) and dysfunctions (e.g., types of diabetes, genetic disorders), a situation often reflecting an evolutionary process of duplication and coopting of mechanistic components. It is also worth emphasizing that the fact that an operationally defined measured/manipulated variable expectation is shown to have a biological referent does not automatically entail the elimination of a theoretically defined construct expectation associated with this variable. The theoretical construct may survive, although it is now associated with a biological activity.

References

  • Adolphs, R., & Anderson, D. J. (2018). The neuroscience of emotion: A new synthesis. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich, J. (1995). Correlations genuine and spurious in pearson and yule. Statistical Science, 10(4), 364–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asmundson, G. J. G., & Wright, K. D. (2004). Biopsychosocial approaches to pain. In T. Hadjistavropoulos & K. D. Craig (Eds.), Pain: Psychological perspectives. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baetu, T. M. (2012). Filling in the mechanistic details: Two-variable experiments as tests for constitutive relevance. European journal for philosophy of science, 2(3), 337–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baetu, T. M. (2019a). Mechanisms in molecular biology. In G. Ramsey & M. Ruse (Eds.), Elements in the philosophy of biology. Cambridge University Press.

  • Baetu, T. M. (2019b). On pain experience, interdisciplinary integration and levels of description, explanation and reality. Synthese, 196(8), 3231–3250.

  • Baetu, T. M. (2020). Causal inference in biomedical research. Biology and Philosophy, 35, 43.

  • Baumgartner, M., & Gebharter, A. (2016). Constitutive relevance, mutual manipulability, and fat-handedness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67, 731–756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Routledge.

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bevilacqua, F. (1993). Helmholtz’s Ueber die Erhaltung der Kraft: The emergence of a theoretical physicist. In D. Cahan (Ed.), Hermann Von Helmholtz and the foundations of nineteenth-century science. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2006). Reducing mind to molecular pathways: Explicating the reductionism implicit in current cellular and molecular neuroscience. Synthese, 151, 411–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J., & Woodward, J. (1988). Saving the phenomena. The Philosophical Review, 97(3), 303–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. E., & Waloga, G. (1981). Effects of cyclic nucleotides and calcium ions on bufo rods. In W. H. Miller (Ed.), Molecular mechanisms of photoreceptor transduction (pp. 369?380). Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2008). Causation in psychiatry. In K. Kendler, & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry (pp. 196–216). Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corns, J. (2012). Pain is not a natural kind. ProQuest Dissertations Publishing.

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). Search of biological mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., Glennan, S., & Povich, M. (2021). Constitutive relevance & mutual manipulability revisited. Synthese, 199, 8807–8828.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: Essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (1992). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fu, Y. (2020). Phototransduction in rods and cones. In H. Kolb, E. Fernandez, & R. Nelson (Eds.), Webvision: The organization of the retina and visual system (pp. 631–668) University of Utah Health Sciences Center.

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

  • Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford University Press.

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hagins, W. A., Penn, R. D., & Yoshikami, S. (1970). Dark current and photocurrent in retinal rods. Biophysical Journal, 10(5), 380–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagins, W. A., & Yoshikami, S. (1974). A role for Ca2 + in excitation of retinal rods and cones. Experimental Eye Research, 18(3), 299–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Handwerker, H. O. (1996). Sixty years of C-Fiber recordings from animal and human skin nerves: Historical notes. In T. Kumazawa (Ed.), The polymodal pathological pain receptor: A gateway to pathological pain (pp. 39–51). L. Kruger and K. Mfzumura.

  • Hardcastle, V. (1999). The myth of pain. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harinen, T. (2014). Mutual manipulability and causal inbetweenness. Synthese, 195(1), 34–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haxby, J. V. (2012). Multivariate pattern analysis of fMRI: The early beginnings. NeuroImage, 62, 852–855.

  • Hernán, M. A., & Robins, J. M. (2020). Causal inference: What if. Chapman & Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. C., Perez, J. M., Forrow, L., Fregni, F., & Pascual-Leone, A. (2011). Transcranial magnetic stimulation: A historical evaluation and future prognosis of therapeutically relevant ethical concerns. Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(2), 137–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • IASP (2020). Task force on taxonomy. Pain Terms and Definitions. Available from https://www.iasp-pain.org/resources/terminology

  • Illari, P. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Integrating the ontic and epistemic. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 237–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanisms are real and local. In P. McKay Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 818–844). Oxford University Press.

  • Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(1), 119–135.

  • Kaiser, M. I., & Krickel, B. (2017). The metaphysics of constitutive mechanistic phenomena. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(3), 745–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J. H., & Jessell, T. M. (2000). Principles of neuroscience (4th ed.). McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., & Campbell, J. (2009). Interventionist causal models in psychiatry: Repositioning the mind-body problem. Psychological Medicine, 39, 881–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism or something near enough. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krickel, B. (2018). The mechanical world: The metaphysical commitments of the new mechanistic approach. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leighton, J. P. (2010). Internal validity. In N. J. Salkind (Ed.), Encyclopedia of research design (pp. 619–622). SAGE.

  • Leuridan, B. (2012). Three problems for the mutual manipulability account of constitutive relevance in mechanisms. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 399–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, D. G., Xue, T., & Yau, K. W. (2008). How vision begins: An odyssey. Proceedings to the National Academy of Sciences, 105(29), 9855–9862.

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, J. W. (1997). Phenomena and patterns in data sets. Erkenntnis, 47, 217–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCaffery, M. (1968). Nursing practice theories related to cognition, bodily pain, and man-environment interactions. UCLA Students Store.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melzack, R. (2001). Pain and the neuromatrix in the brain. Journal of Dental Education, 65(12), 1378–1382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, W. H., Gorman, R. E., & Bitensky, M. W. (1971). Cyclic adenosine monophosphate: Function in photoreceptors. Science, 174(4006), 295–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, W. H., & Nicol, G. D. (1979). Evidence that cyclic gmp regulates membrane potential in rod photoreceptors. Nature, 280, 64–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J., Glymour, M., & Jewell, N. P. (2016). Causal inference in statistics: A primer. Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, D. D., & Barrell, J. J. (2012). Inner experience and neuroscience: Merging both perspectives. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rainsford, K. (2011). Fifty years since the discovery of ibuprofen. Inflammopharmacology, 19(6), 293–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainville, P. (2008). Hypnosis and the analgesic effect of suggestions. Pain, 134(1), 1–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainville, P., Duncan, G. H., Price, D.D., Carrier, B., & Bushnell, M. C. (1997). Pain affect encoded in human anterior cingulate but not somatosensory cortex. Science, 277(5328), 968–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romero, F. (2015). Why there isn’t inter-level causation in mechanisms. Synthese, 192, 3731–3755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. (2021). Being you: A new science of consciousness. Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shadish, W. R., Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (2002). Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for generalized causal inference. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (1993). Causation, prediction and search. Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomita, T. (1970). Electrical activity of vertebrate photoreceptors. Quarterly Reviews of Biophysics, 3(2), 179–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (1998). Measuring the intentional world: realism, naturalism, and quantitative methods in the behavioral sciences. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velmans, M. (2009). Understanding consciousness (2nd ed.). Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wager, T. D., Atlas, L. Y., Lindquist, M. A., Roy, M., Woo, C.-W., & Kross, E. (2013). An fMRI-based neurologic signature of physical pain. New England Journal of Medicine, 368(15), 1388–1397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woo, C. W., Schmidt, L., Krishnan, A., Jepma, M., Roy, M., Lindquist, M. A., Atlas, L. Y., & Wager, T. D. (2017). Quantifying cerebral contributions to pain beyond nociception. Nature Communications. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms14211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff, M. L., Bownds, D., Green, S. H., Morrisey, J. L., & Shedlovsky, A. (1977). Guanosine 3’,5’-Cyclic monophosphate and the in vitro physiology of frog photoreceptor membranes. Journal of General Physiology, 69(5), 667–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69, S366–S377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2008). Cause and explanation in psychiatry: An interventionist perspective. In Kendler, K., & Parnas, J. (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry: Explanation phenomenology and nosology. Johns Hopkins University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2011). Mechanisms revisited. Synthese, 183(3), 409–427.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by SSHRC Grant # 430-2020-0654.

Funding

(if any): SSHRC Grant # 430-2020-0654.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tudor M. Baetu.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

There are no financial or non-financial competing interests to report.

Ethical approval

Not applicable.

Informed consent

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baetu, T.M. A mechanistic guide to reductive physicalism. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 12, 62 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00489-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00489-3

Navigation