Log in

Reasoning and commitment

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue for a commitment-discharging condition of reasoning, according to which to engage in reasoning is to discharge the theoretical and practical commitments one has undertaken. I highlight the ways in which this condition is distinct from other proposals, particularly the Taking Condition, and argue that it can explain certain intuitions about reasoning that otherwise remain elusive. In particular, I argue that the commitment-discharging condition can provide a unified account of attitude-formation and premise-discharging reasoning as well as practical and theoretical reasoning. It also provides a novel way to evade the regress that bedevils many accounts of inference.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price includes VAT (Canada)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, I use “reasoning” and “inferring” interchangeably.

  2. As is clear, all such norms are formulated objectively. But the norms can be also formulated subjectively. For example, one is entitled to undertake a cognitive commitment if one has evidence for it. Or one might abandon a cognitive commitment only if one finds evidence against it. Of course, I accept that such formulations are also correct. But I think the objective formulations are more fundamental and that they can also explain the subjective formulation. For example, it is because ‘cognitive commitment ought to be true’ that ‘you ought to have evidence for your cognitive commitments’ (see for example Wedgwood, 2002, p. 276).

  3. Marcus (2021) offers a way to avoid the regress that has some affinities with my view. As he puts it, “I address the problem of regress by arguing that possession of the concept of entailment includes the knowledge that if p entails q, then the truth of p guarantees the truth of q. Thus, the belief that (p and pq) → q is already part of what it is to believe the premises {p, pq}” (pp. 110–111). As is clear, for Marcus it is part of possessing the concept of entailment that one believes the conclusion, while on my account it is a constitutive norm of the concept of belief. So while Marcus focuses on the content of premises, I focus on the force of the premises, namely the attitude that is held towards the content. One obvious advantage of my view is that I can explain why supposition, but not imagination, behaves like belief in theoretical reasoning. This is so because such attitudes have a similar normative constitution. On Marcus’s view, it should be part of the very concept of entailment that only belief and supposition, and not imagination, are subject to this rule of reasoning—which is somehow weird. This is further to the fact that my account is independently motivated by the committive conception of belief and its fulfillment norm.

References

  • Audi, P. (2015). Explanation and explication. In C. Daly (Ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of philosophical methods (pp. 208–230). Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Baldwin, T. (2007). The normative character of belief. In M. Green, & J. N. Williams (Eds.), Moore’s paradox: New Essays on Belief, rationality, and the first person (pp. 76–89). Oxford University press.

  • Bilgrami, A. (2004). Intentionality and norms. In De M. Caro, & D. McArthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 125–151). Harvard University press.

  • Bilgrami, A. (2006). Self-knowledge and resentment. Harvard University press.

  • Blake-Turner, C. (2020). The hereby-commit account of inference. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 100(1), 86–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, p (2014). What is inference? Philosophical Studies, 169, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University press.

  • Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Broome, J. (2014). Comments on Boghossian. Philosophical Studies, 169, 19–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bykvist, K., & Hattiagandi, A. (2013). Belief, Truth, and blindspots. In T. Chan (Ed.), The Aim of Belief (pp. 100–122). Oxford University press.

  • Carroll, L. (1895). What the Tortoise Said to Achilles. Mind, 4(14), 278–280.

  • Coliva, A. (2015). How to commit Moore’s paradox. Journal of philosophy, 112(4), 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coliva, A. (2016). The varieties of self-knowledge. Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Dogramaci, S. (2013). Intuitions for inferences. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 371–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hlobil, U. (2019a). Inferring by attaching force. Australasian Journal of philosophy, 97(4), 701–714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hlobil, U. (2019b). We cannot infer by accepting testimony. Philosophical Studies, 176, 2589–2598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2007). Moore’s Paradox and the Norm of Belief. In S. Nuccetelli, & G. Seay (Eds.), Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays on Epistemology and Ethics (pp. 142–157). Clarendon press.

  • Kazemi, A. (2020). Propositional attitudes as commitments: Unleashing some constraints. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 59(3), 437–457. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0012217320000098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazemi, A. (2021). Commitment, norm-governedness and Guidance. Acta Analytica, 36, 213–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazemi, A. (2022). Still committed to the normativity of Folk psychology. Philosophical Explorations, 25(1), 58–74. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2021.1963820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazemi, A. (2023). The norms of belief as the norms of commitment: A case for pluralism. The Southern Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (2002). Commitment and change of View. In J. L. Bermudez, & A. Millar (Eds.), Reason and nature, Essays in the theory of rationality (pp. 209–232). Oxford University press.

  • Marcus, E. (2021). Belief, inference, and the self-conscious mind. Oxford University press.

  • McHugh, C., & Way, J. (2016). Against the taking Condition. Philosophical Issues, 26, 314–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, C., & Way, J. (2018). What is reasoning? Mind, 127(505), 167–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2004). Understanding people: Normativity and rationalizing explanations. Oxford University press.

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and Estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton University press.

  • Neta, R. (2013). What is an inference? Philosophical Issues: A Supplement to Noûs, 23, 388–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1964). How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’. The Philosophical Review, 73, 43–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1967). Form and content in ethical theory. Department of philosophy, University of Kansas.

  • Shah, N. (2008). How Action governs intention. Philosopher’s Imprint, 8(5), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N., & Velleman, D. (2005). Doxastic deliberation. Philosophical Review, 114, 497–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shpall, S. (2014). Moral and rational commitment. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 146–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). No norm needed: On the aim of belief. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 499–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tebben, N. (2019). Knowledge requires commitment (instead of belief). Philosophical Studies, 176(2), 321–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valaris, M. (2014). Reasoning and regress. Mind, 123(489), 101–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valaris, M. (2017). What inference might be. Synthese, 194(6), 2007–2024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2002). The Aim of Belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 267–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2006). The normative force of reasoning. Noûs, 40(4), 660–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2014). Comment on Paul Boghossian, ‘What is inference’. Philosophical Studies, 169, 27–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for Synthese for their perceptive comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alireza Kazemi.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kazemi, A. Reasoning and commitment. Synthese 202, 91 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04308-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04308-x

Keywords

Navigation