Log in

Locke’s Children? Rousseau and the Beans (Beings?) of the Colonial Learner

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Rousseau’s story about Emile having his first moral lesson in property rights by planting beans in a garden plot has educationally been discussed from various perspectives. What remains unexplored in such readings, however, is the connection of the theory of the natural learner with the Lockean rationalization of appropriation of land through cultivation. We will show that this connection forms the subtext of the ‘beans’ episode and grounds the rich and complex textual operations that give to the episode a strong political character. The aim is to unearth the common, colonial cause that the ideas of the natural learner, property as original relation to land and contractuality may make in Locke-inspired, early modern pedagogy and to explore the ambivalences in Rousseau’s text that are thus created.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Gay-White and Wadewitz (2009) explain, Locke and Rousseau’s pedagogical writings provided much of the theory that underpins the theatricality of artificial situations that generate a socializing aesthetic experience.

  2. However, Lines detects a paradox or, perhaps, a contradiction in Rousseau’s employing an artificial situation for effecting natural learning: ‘Thus Emile suffers the natural consequences of his bad actions. That may be a good idea, but is such a manipulated scenario really a natural experience?’ (Lines 2009, p. 52, emph added).

  3. Amongst other things that Rousseau wants Emile to learn from peasants’ ways are: some eating habits; speaking regulation; and good grasp of few and manageable ideas (Rousseau 2009).

  4. A. Rosenberg identifies a coincidence of Rousseau’s views on agriculture only with a long tradition revived by the physiocrats of Rousseau’s day. But Locke’s views are also similar as we will see later on.

  5. Arneil is based mainly on paragraph 37 of the Two Treatises. More generally, through a discussion of ample textual evidence she concludes: ‘it must be recognized that natural rights theory, particularly with regard to the origins of private property, has specific historical roots in England’s colonization of the new world’ (Arneil 1994, p. 609).

  6. For more on the connection between the Lockean utopianization of the child as a natural learner and colonial and gendered assumptions, see, Gregoriou and Papastephanou (2013).

  7. Ferguson sees this episode pedagogically interesting amongst other things ‘because it exactly inverts the Lockean model’. Whereas Locke counsels that adults should continually extend credit to underwrite children’s efforts, ‘Rousseau’s account involves substituting a vision of an infinite series of losses for Locke’s vision of an infinite projection of credit’ (Ferguson 1984, p. 81).

  8. We borrow Derrida’s term, here. See, Derrida (1994).

  9. Malta, the island, that is evoked through the name of the fruit, was at the time of the writing of Emile still under the Knights’ ‘colonial’ control before passing to French hands by Napoleon’s conquest in 1798 and then to British colonial rule in 1814.

  10. In Rousseau’s words, Emile as an adult ‘most often roams through the surrounding countryside. He pursues his natural history; he observes and examines the earth, its products and its cultivation’ (2009, p. 622).

  11. Rousseau’s ambivalence regarding peasants and savages as others to his ideal ‘man’, e.g. that the savage is presented as craftier than the dull peasant (Rousseau 2009, p. 56), while, at another instance, Rousseau’s utopian subject must work like the peasant in order to avoid becoming lazy like a savage (p. 353) is an interesting and relevant issue, yet for another article, for reasons of space. It is important to stress here, however, that the colonial spectrology in Rousseau’s text is not confined to the ‘other’ outside borders.

  12. For instance, to restore all men to their primal duties Rousseau suggests that one should ‘begin with Mothers; you will be surprised by the changes you will produce’. For Rousseau, the whole moral order degenerates, as nature becomes quenched in every breast (Rousseau 2009, p. 12).

  13. Unlike hauntology, ontology focuses on the actual that is easily recognizable as existing or valid and easily detectable as the cause or explanation of facts.

  14. According to Francisco (2012, p. 66), this solves the apparent paradox that Rousseau, in Emile, considers learning about property morally so important, whereas in the Discourse on Social Inequality he condemns property as the root of all evil. Indeed, for Rousseau, since there can be no return to the moment when the first man fenced land to make it his own and thus no way to stop him from initiating the institution of property, the only thing left is at least to teach about property in a critical way (ibid, pp. 67–68).

  15. To ‘discover the best rules of society […] would require a superior intelligence who saw all of man’s passions and experienced none of them, who had no relation to our nature yet knew it thoroughly, whose happiness was independent of us and who was nevertheless willing to care for ours […]. It would require gods to give men laws’ (Rousseau 1997, pp. 68–69, emph added). In reality, of course, the law-giver is human, not divine.

  16. Friedrich Ratzel coined the term Lebensraum in 1901; it was then used as a slogan in Germany referring to the unification of the country and the acquisition of colonies, based on the English and French models, and the westward expansion of the United States. Wikipedia source (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebensraum) drawing from Smith (1980).

  17. In a footnote Rousseau explains the following: ‘This is why most children want to have back what they have given and cry when one does not want to return it to them. This no longer occurs when they have gotten a good conception of what a gift is, but then they are more circumspect about giving’ (p. 231).

  18. For the notions of inward and outward patriotism, see, Papastephanou (2013).

  19. In other words: In what sense does the artificiality of the context that Jean–Jacques creates for Emile domesticate the real situations of conflict over the past and its pending debts?

  20. Wikipedia source: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Blood_and_soil

  21. This gruesome expansion of Blut und Boden is surely replete with memory; but this memory cannot be attuned to justice.

  22. For a critical discussion of the association of Rousseau and progressive pedagogy, see Avi Mintz (2012).

  23. For the notion of modern developmentalism and its relation to our globalized world see, Papastephanou et al. (2012).

  24. The term ‘first philosophy’ or prima philosophia designates the science of the being as being which later, in the seventeenth century was called ‘ontology’. See, Apel (1998, p. 43).

  25. For the Rousseau of the Encyclopaedia entry on political economy, ‘the foundation of the social pact is property’. ‘Its first condition is that everyone should be guaranteed the peaceful enjoyment of what he owns’; ‘the right of property [is] the true foundation of political society’ (Rousseau, cf. Pierson, p. 2).

  26. Here, we adapt Ferguson (1984, p. 83).

References

  • Apel, K.-O. (1998). Transcendental semiotics and the paradigms of first philosophy. In M. Papastephanou (Ed.), From a transcendental-semiotic point of view (pp. 43–63). Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneil, B. (1992). John Locke, natural law and colonialism. History of Political Thought XIII, 4, 587–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneil, B. (1994). Trade, plantations, and property: John Locke and the economic defense of colonialism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 55(4), 591–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, A. (1979). Introduction: Emile or on education (trans: Bloom A.). USA: Basic Books.

  • Buchan, B. (2005). The empire of political thought: Civilization, savagery and perceptions of Indigenous government. History of the Human Sciences, 18(2), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambliss, J. J. (1998). Irony in Rousseau’s Emile: Philosophy of education yearbook. http://ojs.ed.uiuc.edu/index.php/pes/article/view/2105/800. Accessed 05 Dec 2012.

  • Coleman, P. (1991). Property and personality in Rousseau’s Emile. Romance Quarterly, 38(3), 301–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, A. (2002). Jean-Jacques Rousseau and exotic Botany. Eighteenth-Century Life, 26(3), 181–201.

  • Derrida, J. (1994). Specters of marx: the state of debt, the work of mourning, and the new international (trans: Kamuf, P.). New York: Routledge.

  • Ferguson, F. (1984). Reading morals: Locke and Rousseau on education and inequality. Representations, 6(2), 66–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francisco, M. de F. S (2012). La Filosofía de la Educación de Rousseau. Una Propuesta de Relectura del Emilio. Revista Educación y Pedagogía, 12, 26–27.

  • Gay-White, P., & Wadewitz, A. (2009). Introduction: ‘Performing the Didactic’. The Lion and the Unicorn, 33(2), 5–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glausser, W. (1990). Three approaches to Locke and the slave trade. Journal of the History of Ideas, 51(2), 199–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregoriou, Z., & Papastephanou, M. (2013). The utopianism of John Locke’s natural learning. Ethics and Education, 8(1), 18–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krejci, H. (2007). The effects of human nature on educational philosophies and the application of educational philosophies. http://gradworks.umi.com/14/50/1450375.html.

  • Lassman, P. (2003). Political theory as Utopia. History of the Human Sciences, 16(1), 49–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lines, P. M. (2009). Shackling the imagination: Education for virtue in Plato and Rousseau. Humanitas, 22(1–2), 40–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1899). Some thoughts concerning education 1693, with an introduction and notes by R. H. Quick. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1988). In P. Laslett (Ed.) Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Marks, J. (2006). The Divine Instinct? Rousseau and Conscience. The Review of Politics, 68, 564–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marks, J. (2012). Rousseau’s critique of Locke’s education for liberty. The Journal of Politics, 74(3), 694–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mintz, A. I. (2012). The happy and suffering student? Rousseau’s Emile and the path not taken in progressive educational thought. Educational Theory, 62(3), 249–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, M. P. (1985). Rousseau’s novel education in the Emile. Political Theory, 13(4), 535–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papastephanou, M. (2013). Inward and outward patriotism. Review of European Studies, 5(2), 124–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papastephanou, M., Christou, M., & Gregoriou, Z. (2012). Globalisation, the challenge of educational synchronisation and teacher education. Globalization, Societies and Education, 10(2), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peeters, O. (2012). Educating liberty: Rousseauvian influences on the progressive education systems of Maria Montessori and Helen Parkhurst. http://igitur-archive.library.uu.nl. Accessed 05 Dec 2012.

  • Pierson, C. (2010). Rousseau on property: A heroic failure? http://www.psa.ac.uk/2010/UploadedPaperPDFs/1009_1082.pdf. Accessed 05 Dec 2012.

  • Rosenberg, A. (1995). Food for thought in Rousseau’s Emile. In Lumen: Selected proceedings from the Canadian Society for eighteenth-century studies/Lumen: travaux choisis de la Société canadienne d’étude du dix-huitième siècle, 14, 97–108. doi:10.7202/1012511ar.

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1997). In V. Gourevitch (Ed.), The social contract and other later political writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (2009). Emile or on education (includes Emile and Sophie or the solitaries) (trans and eds: Kelly, C., Bloom, A.). Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.

  • Shklar, J. (1985 [1969]). Men and citizens: A study of Rousseau’s social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Simon, J. (1995). Natural freedom and moral autonomy: Emile as parent, teacher and citizen. History of Political Thought, 16(1), 21–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. D. (1980). Friedrich Ratzel and the origins of lebensraum. German Studies Review, 3(1), 51–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tröhler, D. (2012). Rousseau’s Emile or the fear of passions. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 31, 477–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wain, K. (Ed.). (2011). Education domestic and solitary. In On Rousseau. Key thinkers in education, (Vol. 3, pp. 21–38). Amsterdam: Springer.

  • Wright, N. (n.d.). The visionary’s blind spot: Rousseau’s presentations of private property in the discourse on inequality and Emile. http://cas.illinoisstate.edu. Accessed 05 Dec 2012.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marianna Papastephanou.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Papastephanou, M., Gregoriou, Z. Locke’s Children? Rousseau and the Beans (Beings?) of the Colonial Learner. Stud Philos Educ 33, 463–480 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-013-9397-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-013-9397-9

Keywords

Navigation