A Methodological Problem of Choice for 4E Research

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Situated Cognition Research

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 23))

Abstract

The 4E approaches have been frequently linked to the claim that they fundamentally change how we theoretically analyze and empirically investigate cognitive phenomena. Despite this aspiration, the methodology of 4E researchers received surprisingly little attention, although the envisaged change of mainstream cognitive studies presupposes elaborated methodical competencies. This chapter argues that a methodology is necessary for the 4Es. However, several preliminary considerations need to precede a methodological analysis of the branch. It is claimed that methodological analyses of 4E research first need to answer the problem of choice whether to support a version of explanatory pluralism or explanatory unification. The answer to this problem significantly influences how a methodology can be developed. The problem can only be properly met, however, if the different versions of pluralist and unificationist positions are related so that we can understand where exactly they diverge or overlap. Below, the spectrum of integration is introduced, which suggests a relation between pluralist and unificationist views. The spectrum is a provisional guide to a 4E methodology as it invites 4E researchers to place themselves within this spectrum and approach methodological and methodical questions from there.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is important to note that Miłkowski (2016a) distinguishes between integration and unification in a different manner. While, for him, integration is the process of combining multiple explanations in a coherent manner, unification is the process of develo** general, simple, elegant explanations. His account of integration is therefore different from the one in this article that suggests that the intensity of integration is a measurement for unification.

References

  • Albertazzi, L. (2019). Experimental phenomenology. What it is and what it is not. Synthese, 198, 2191–2212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. J. (2019). Eliminative pluralism and integrative alternatives: The case of species. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 657–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., & Laland, K. N. (2013). Tinbergen’s four questions: An appreciation and an update. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 28, 712–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2019). Analysing network models to make discoveries about biological mechanisms. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70, 459–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2020). Hierarchy and levels: Analysing networks to study mechanisms in molecular biology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 375(1796), 20190320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2008). From reduction back to higher levels. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 30(30). Retrieved (24.07.2023) from https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8zn5q0j8

  • Bekoff, M. (1999). Cognitive ethology. In W. Bechtel & G. Graham (Eds.), A companion to cognitive science. Blackwell Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Bechtel, W. (2021). Mechanism, autonomy and biological explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 36, 53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bromberger, S. (1966). Why-questions. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Mind and cosmos: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy (pp. 86–111). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carls-Diamante, S. (2019). Make up your mind: Octopus cognition and hybrid explanations. Synthese, 199(Suppl 1), 143–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casper, M. O. (2019). Social enactivism. On situating high-level cognitive states and processes. De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casper, M. O., & Haueis, P. (2022). Stuck in between. Phenomenology’s explanatory dilemma and its role in experimental practice. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 22(7), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2013). Radical embodied cognitive science. Review of General Psychology, 17(2), 145–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world back together again. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015a). Embodied prediction. Open mind. Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015b). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015c). Predicting peace: The end of the representation wars. A reply to Michael Madary. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind: 7(R). MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570979

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2019). Levels of mechanisms: A field guide to the hierarchical structure of the world. In S. Robins, J. Symons, & P. Calvo (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of psychology (pp. 427–439). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Tabery, J. (2015). Mechanisms in science. Retrieved (01.04.2023) from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/science-mechanisms/

  • Dale, R., Dietrich, E., & Chemero, A. (2009). Explanatory pluralism in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 33(5), 739–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44(1), 43–64. https://doi.org/10.1086/288723

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Jong, H. L. (2001). Introduction: A symposium on explanatory pluralism. Theory & Psychology, 11(6), 731–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feest, U. (2012). Exploratory experiments, concept formation, and theory construction in psychology. Scientific concepts and investigative practice, 3, 167–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2003). Phenomenology and experimental design. Toward a phenomenologically enlightened experimental science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 85–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017b). The past, present, and future of time-consciousness – From Husserl to Varela and beyond. Constructivist Foundations, 13(1), 91–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2020). The phenomenological mind. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2011). Selected effects and causal role functions in the brain: The case for an etiological approach to neuroscience. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 547–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gervais, R. (2021). The multiplicity of explanation in cognitive science. Foundations of Science, 26(4), 1089–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gładziejewski, P. (2019). Mechanistic unity of the predictive mind. Theory & Psychology, 29(5), 657–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldinger, S. D., Papesh, M. H., Barnhart, A. S., Hansen, W. A., & Hout, M. C. (2016). The poverty of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23, 959–978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. A. (2004). Conceptualizing the (dis)unity of science. Philosophy of Science, 71(2), 133–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halonen, I., & Hintikka, J. (1999). Unification: It’s magnificent but is it explanation? Synthese, 120(1), 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, V. (1992). Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences. Philosophy of Science, 59, 408–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haueis, P. (2014). Meeting the brain on its own terms. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausmann, D. M. (1993). Linking causal and explanatory asymmetry. Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 435–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohol, M. (2021). Cognitive science: An interdisciplinary approach to mind and cognition. In B. Brożek, M. Jakubiec, & P. Urbańczyk (Eds.), Perspectives on interdisciplinarity (pp. 33–55). Copernicus Center Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2020). New directions in predictive processing. Mind & Language, 35(2), 209–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2014). Neural representations not needed-no more pleas, please. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13(2), 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., Kirchhoff, M. D., & Myin, E. (2014). Extensive enactivism: Why keep it all in? Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D., & Bekoff, M. (1992). On aims and methods of cognitive ethology. PSA: proceedings of the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1992(2), 110–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, A. (1962/2017). The conduct of inquiry. Methodology for behavioral science. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Bechtel, W. (2011). Dynamical models: An alternative or complement to mechanistic explanations? Topics in Cognitive Science, 3(2), 438–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K., Millson, J., & Risjord, M. (2021). Inference, explanation, and asymmetry. Synthese, 198, 929–953.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D., & Kiverstein, J. (2020). Attuning to the world: The diachronic constitution of the extended conscious mind. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 1966.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D., & Robertson, I. (2018). Enactivism and predictive processing: A non-representational view. Philosophical Explorations, 21(2), 264–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. Philosophical Review, 93, 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Clark, A. (2009). Introduction: Mind embodied, embedded, enacted: One church or many? Topoi, 28, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Körner, A., Topolinski, S., & Strack, F. (2015). Routes to embodiment. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krickel, B. (2018). The mechanical world. Studies in brain and mind.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krickel, B. (2020). Extended cognition, the new mechanists’ mutual manipulability criterion, and the challenge of trivial extendedness. Mind & Language, 35(4), 539–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1968). Criticism and the methodology of scientific research programmes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 69, 149–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, M., & Chemero, A. (2014). Structure and application of dynamical models in cognitive science. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 36, 809–814.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1989). From theories to research traditions. In B. A. Brody & R. E. Grandy (Eds.), Readings in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 368–379). Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2016). Pragmatism and the pragmatic turn in cognitive science. In A. K. Engel, K. J. Friston, & D. Kragic (Eds.), The pragmatic turn. Towards action-oriented viewers in cognitive science (pp. 215–234). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M. (2016a). A mechanistic account of computational explanation in cognitive science and computational neuroscience. Computing and Philosophy: Selected Papers from IACAP, 2014, 191–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M. (2016b). Unification strategies in cognitive science. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 48(1), 13–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M., & Hohol, M. (2021). Explanations in cognitive science: Unification versus pluralism. Synthese, 199, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M., & Nowakowski, P. (2021). Representational unification in cognitive science: Is embodied cognition a unifying perspective? Synthese, 199(1), 67–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M., Clowes, R., Rucińska, Z., Przegalińska, A., Zawidzki, T., Krueger, J., et al. (2018). From wide cognition to mechanisms: A silent revolution. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 2393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M., Hohol, M., & Nowakowski, P. (2019). Mechanisms in psychology: The road towards unity? Theory & Psychology, 29(5), 567–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2002). Integrative pluralism. Biology and Philosophy, 17, 55–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2000). Unifying scientific theories: Physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Muszynski, E., & Malaterre, C. (2021). A roadmap to explanatory pluralism: Introduction to the topical collection ‘The Biology of Behaviour’. Synthese, 199(1), 1777–1789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. Problems in the logic of explanation. Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1973). You can’t play 20 questions with nature and win: Projective comments on the papers of this symposium. In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information processing (pp. 283–308). Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., De Bruin, L., & Gallagher, S. (2018). The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, K. S. (2006). Discussions dynamical explanation in cognitive science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 37, 139–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orlandi, N. (2018). Predictive perceptual systems. Synthese, 195(6), 2367–2386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2020). Neurocognitive mechanisms: Explaining biological cognition. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Povich, M., & Craver, C. F. (2017). Mechanistic levels, reduction, and emergence. In S. Glennan & P. M. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 185–197). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, P., & Aydede, M. (Eds.). (2009). The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2015). The social roots of normativity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Science, 14, 673–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2007). The embodied cognition research programme. Philosophy Compass, 2(2), 338–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2010). Embodied cognition. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2013). Constraints on localization and decomposition as explanatory strategies in the biological sciences. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 958–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J., Gapenne, O., & Di Paolo, E. A. (Eds.). (2010). Enaction. Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S. D. (2021). Two kinds of explanatory integration in cognitive science. Synthese, 198(5), 4573–4601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, H., & Vickers, P. (2017). Conceptual fragmentation and the rise of eliminativism. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7(1), 17–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Villalobos, M., & Dewhurst, J. (2017). Why post-cognitivism does not (necessarily) entail anti-computationalism. Adaptive Behavior, 25, 117–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Model and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183, 313–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2010). In defense of extended functionalism. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 245–270). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78(2), 238–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark-Oliver Casper .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Casper, MO. (2023). A Methodological Problem of Choice for 4E Research. In: Casper, MO., Artese, G.F. (eds) Situated Cognition Research. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39744-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation