Log in

Evolution of Risk-Taking Behaviour and Status Preferences in Anti-coordination Games

  • Published:
Dynamic Games and Applications Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper analyses how risk-taking behaviour and preferences over consumption rank can emerge when individuals have an incentive to coordinate their actions. Using an evolutionary game theory framework, it is shown that when ex-ante homogeneous individuals face a strategic interaction where they benefit from choosing distinct actions, i.e. an anti-coordination game, stable types must be willing to accept risky gambles over consumption to differentiate themselves. This is the case despite an assumed concavity of the objective function, which makes any gamble costly in expectation. Consumption differences act as a form of costly communication that allows for coordination. More specifically, it is shown that when individuals have access to any fair consumption lottery, there exists a neutrally stable equilibrium where individuals choose a risky lottery and condition their action in the anti-coordination game on relative consumption. Furthermore, the evolutionarily optimal risk-taking behaviour can be induced by preferences over consumption rank. This suggests status preferences might have evolved and are salient in settings where miscoordination is particularly detrimental.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Germany)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of Data and Materials

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For instance, Kuhn et al. [27] demonstrate that the neighbours of lottery winners significantly increase their expenditure on cars. More generally, this notion of conspicuous consumption goes back to Veblen [43]. See, for instance, Frank [16] and Mas and Moretti [29] for empirical examples for the economic importance of positional concerns, as well as (among many others) Corneo and Jeanne [10], Hopkins and Kornienko [22], and Becker et al. [6] for theoretical treatments. Heffetz and Frank [18] provide a detailed survey.

  2. Throughout this paper, ‘risk’ refers to idiosyncratic risk. In an evolutionary context, this is distinct from risks that are correlated across individuals. Attitudes towards such aggregate risk are the focus of attention in, for example, Robson [38] and Heller and Nehama [19].

  3. This does not have to be conflict involving the risk of injury but, for instance in a biological context, can also be the case of a ritualized display that requires effort, as in Maynard Smith [30], or a task, for example a joint hunt, that might fail.

  4. Asymmetry in taking-roles might even be beneficial on a global scale, as suggested in Acemoglu et al. [2].

  5. See Maynard Smith [31] for various examples where size determines outcomes in asymmetric interactions even though size is not necessarily correlated with the success in conflict. For instance, Riechert [35] presents a particular example where spiders react to relative size as a cue in bilateral interactions. In the context of the model presented here, differences in consumption could lead to observable differences which can then be used to correlate actions.

  6. Interpreted loosely, the lotteries could also be a series of antagonistic interactions whose probabilistic outcomes determine access to resources but avoid more serious conflict, as observed in various animal societies. For instance, many primates establish a social hierarchy through dominance behaviour that then determines access to resources like mating partners. See, for example, Hausfater [17] for a discussion of hierarchies in male baboons and Abbott and George [1] for hierarchies in female marmosets. More closely related, Ellis et al. [14] provide a detailed analysis of risk-taking in young adults.

  7. See also Robson [40] for a detailed survey.

  8. Suppose the risky outcome is such that \(c_l'=4.5\) and \(c_h'=5.25\), with \(c_h'\) twice as likely as \(c_l'\) (i.e. the risky activity constitutes a fair gamble). Then, \(f_{c}' \approx 3.52 > f_{m}' \approx 3.40\). In fact, \(f_{c}' > f_{m}'\) even for costly (unfair) gambles as long as \(\Pr (c_h') > 0.54...\).

  9. Players here are anonymous, meaning the game has no (ex-ante) uncorrelated asymmetries in the sense of Maynard Smith and Parker [32].

  10. Formally, a player’s response to a given message can be characterized a function \(\rho : M \rightarrow A\). If \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {R}}}}\limits \) is the set of all such functions, the set of strategies (given the player’s own consumption level) is \(\Phi :=\Delta (\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {R}}}}\limits )\). Since the chosen strategy in the stage game generally depends on a player’s realization, the strategy space for all possible lottery realizations is \(\Phi ^M\), where M is the set of realizations.

  11. See Kreps [26], Definition 5.10. If \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) contains all fair lotteries with their support bounded by some interval \(V \subset \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits \), we can just replace \(\Delta (\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits )\) by \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \), which is closed under convex combinations.

  12. Recall that since f is only defined over \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits _+\), we assume an individual with consumption allocation c has only access to lotteries that are bounded below by c.

  13. This corresponds to an opponent with endowment \(c_0\) that selects a lottery \(L_G\), where \(L_G\) is defined such that \(L_G(x) \equiv G(c_0 + x)\), for all x such that \(c_0 + x\) is in the support of G.

  14. Note that these are a slightly adjusted version of the payoffs shown in Table 4.

  15. The proof in Appendix A also treats the discontinuous case.

  16. ’Small’ is determined by the equilibrium consumption distribution. If mutants choose a lottery with density \(\lambda _L'\), then this is compatible with an (aggregate) equilibrium distribution \(\lambda _L\) if \(\epsilon \cdot \lambda _L'(c) \le \lambda _L(c),\; \forall c \in M\).

  17. This relies on all gains from randomization being realized. If the set of lotteries is restricted to some costly lotteries or does not include the (fair) lottery that renders expected fitness linear, F(c|G) might be convex in equilibrium over some range and a uniquely optimal lottery choice in \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) might exist.

  18. See, for instance, Weibull [44][p.37] for the definition of evolutionary stable strategies.

  19. Note that \(\ln \) maps to \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits \) rather than \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits _+\) and is thus, strictly, speaking, not a fitness function. It is chosen here merely for expositional purposes. Equivalent results can be shown with ‘true’ fitness functions.

  20. Next to the large body of economic literature on how relative income and conspicuous consumption affect individuals’ behaviour, there is also anthropological evidence for the importance of status and its economics consequences. See, for instance, Johnson [24], on how prestige affects social interactions among the Enga people.

  21. This is shown formally in Appendix B.

References

  1. Abbott D, George L (1991) Reproductive consequences of changing social status in female common marmosets. In: Box H (ed) Primate responses to environmental change. Springer, Amsterdam, pp 295–309

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Acemoglu D, Robinson J, Verdier T (2012) Can’t we all be more like Scandinavians? Asymmetric growth and institutions in an interdependent world. Working paper. National Bureau of Economic Research

  3. Alger I, Weibull J (2013) Homo Moralis-preference evolution under incomplete information and assortative matching. Econometrica 81(6):2269–2302

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Ball S, Eckel C, Grossman P, Zame W (2001) Status in markets. Q J Econ 116(1):161–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Banerjee A, Weibull J (2000) Neutrally stable outcomes in cheap-talk coordination games. Games Econom Behav 32(1):1–24

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Becker G, Murphy K, Werning I (2005) The equilibrium distribution of income and the market for status. J Polit Econ 113(2):282–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Clark A, Westergård-Nielsen N, Kristensen N (2009) Economic satisfaction and income rank in small neighbourhoods. J Eur Econ Assoc 7(2):519–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Clingingsmith D, Sheremeta R (2018) Status and the demand for visible goods: experimental evidence on conspicuous consumption. Exp Econ 21(4):877–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Cole H, Mailath G, Postlewaite A (1992) Social norms, savings behavior, and growth. J Polit Econ 100(6):1092–1125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Corneo G, Jeanne O (1998) Social organization, status, and savings behavior. J Public Econ 70(1):37–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Dekel E, Scotchmer S (1999) On the evolution of attitudes towards risk in winner-take-all games. J Econ Theory 87(1):125–143

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Dekel E, Ely J, Yilankaya O (2007) Evolution of preferences. Rev Econ Stud 74(3):685–704

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Eckel C, Ball S (1998) The economic value of status. J Socio Econ 27(4):495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Ellis B, Del Giudice M, Dishion T, Figueredo AJ, Gray P, Griskevicius V, Hawley P, Jacobs J, James J, Volk A et al (2012) The evolutionary basis of risky adolescent behavior: implications for science, policy, and practice. Dev Psychol 48(3):598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Fisher R (1915) The evolution of sexual preference. Eugen Rev 7(3):184

    Google Scholar 

  16. Frank R (1985) Choosing the right pond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hausfater G (1975) Dominance and reproduction in baboons: a quantitative analysis. Contrib Primatol 7:145–150

    Google Scholar 

  18. Heffetz O, Frank R (2011) Preferences for status: evidence and economic implications. In: Benhabib J, Bisin A, Jackson M (eds) Handbook of social economics, pp 69–91

  19. Heller Y, Nehama I (2023) Evolutionary foundation for heterogeneity in risk aversion. J Econ Theory 208:105617

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Herold F, Kuzmics C (2020) The evolution of taking roles. J Econ Behav Organ 174:38–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Hofbauer J, Sigmund K (1998) Evolutionary games and population dynamics. Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Hopkins E, Kornienko T (2004) Running to keep in the same place: consumer choice as a game of status. Am Econ Rev 94(4):1085–1107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Hurkens S, Schlag K (2003) Evolutionary insights on the willingness to communicate. Internat J Game Theory 31:511–526

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Johnson A (1989) Horticulturalists: economic behavior in tribes. In: Stuart P (ed) The Oxford handbook of innovation. Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp 49–77

    Google Scholar 

  25. Kojima F, Takahashi S (2007) Anti-coordination games and dynamic stability. Int Game Theory Rev 9(04):667–688

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Kreps D (1988) Notes on the theory of choice. Westview Press

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kuhn P, Kooreman P, Soetevent A, Kapteyn A (2011) The effects of lottery prizes on winners and their neighbors: evidence from the Dutch postcode lottery. Am Econ Rev 101(5):2226–2247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Luttmer E (2005) Neighbors as negatives: relative earnings and well-being. Quart J Econ 120(3):963–1002

    Google Scholar 

  29. Mas A, Moretti E (2009) Peers at work. Am Econ Rev 99(1):112–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Maynard Smith J (1974) The theory of games and the evolution of animal conflicts. J Theor Biol 47(1):209–221

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Maynard Smith J (1979) Game theory and the evolution of behaviour. Proc R Soc Lond B 205(1161):475–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Maynard Smith J, Parker G (1976) The logic of asymmetric contests. Anim Behav 24(1):159–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Patrick W, Raleigh R (1979) Offspring quality and the polygyny threshold: “the sexy son hypothesis’’. Am Naturalist 113(2):201–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Ray D, Robson A (2012) Status, intertemporal choice, and risk-taking. Econometrica 80(4):1505–1531

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  35. Riechert S (1978) Games spiders play: behavioral variability in territorial disputes. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 3(2):135–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Robert A (1974) Subjectivity and correlation in randomized strategies. J Math Econ 1(1):67–96

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  37. Robson A (1992) Status, the distribution of wealth, private and social attitudes to risk. Econometrica 60(4):837–857

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Robson A (1996) A biological basis for expected and non-expected utility. J Econ Theory 68(2):397–424

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  39. Robson A (1996) The evolution of attitudes to risk: lottery tickets and relative wealth. Games Econom Behav 14(2):190–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Robson A (2001) The biological basis of economic behavior. J Econ Lit 39(1):11–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Samuelson L (2004) Information-based relative consumption effects. Econometrica 72(1):93–118

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  42. Selten R (1980) A note on evolutionarily stable strategies in asymmetric animal conflicts. J Theor Biol 84(1):93–101

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. Veblen T (1899) The theory of the leisure class. Macmillan, New York

  44. Weibull J (1995) Evolutionary game theory. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  45. Zink C, Tong Y, Chen Q, Bassett D, Stein J, Meyer-Lindenberg A (2008) Know your place: neural processing of social hierarchy in humans. Neuron 58(2):273–283

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

The project leading to this publication has received funding from the French government under the ‘France 2030’ investment plan managed by the French National Research Agency (ANR-17-EURE-0020) and from the Excellence Initiative of Aix-Marseille University - A*MIDEX.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

The author confirms sole responsibility for the conception of this study, analysis and interpretation of results, and preparation of the manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manuel Staab.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Conflict of interest

The authors have no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article is part of the topical collection “Evolutionary Games and Applications” edited by Christian Hilbe, Maria Kleshnina and Kateřina Staňková.

Appendices

Proofs

Proof of Lemma 1

Define the expected fitness payoff (in the stage game) of a player i with endowment c choosing action h with probability \(\phi _i\) against an opponent j choosing h with probability \(\phi _j\) as:

$$\begin{aligned} \Pi (\phi _i, \phi _j | c) :=\phi _i \, (1-\phi _j) \, f(c,{{\overline{s}}})\! + \!(1-\phi _i) \, \phi _j \, f(c,{\underline{s}}) \!+\! (1-\phi _i-\phi _j+2\phi _i\phi _j)f(c,0). \end{aligned}$$

Suppose now, to the contrary of the claim, that a type \(\tau \) is stable against all \(\tau ' \in {\hat{\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {T}}}}\limits }}\) and there exists a subset of non-identical message combinations \({\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}' \subset M\times M\) such that for all \((c,c') \in {\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\), we have \(\phi _{\tau }(c|c') \in (0,1)\) and \(\lambda _L(c -c_0) \cdot \lambda _L(c'-c_0)>0\), meaning \(\tau \) randomizes between actions for a set of messages with positive measure (given lottery L). Then, either both actions yield the same expected fitness, i.e. \(\Pi (1, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c) = \Pi (0, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c)\), or there is a strict best response, meaning \(\Pi (1, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c) \ne \Pi (0, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c)\). Note that different cases can apply to different subsets of \({\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\).

Suppose first the latter is the case and there is a strict best response for a (sub-)set of message combinations \(\hat{{\underline{M}}}\times \hat{{\underline{M}}}' \subseteq {\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\). We can construct a type \(\tau '\) that has identical preferences over lotteries as \(\tau \), meaning that for any configuration \((\tau , \tau ', \epsilon )\), we have \(L_{\tau }^{\epsilon } = L_{\tau '}^{\epsilon }\), with \(L_{\tau }^{\epsilon }\) the lottery choice of a type \(\tau \) given the configuration. Furthermore, let the strategy of a type \(\tau '\) in the stage game be as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \arg \max _{x \in \{0,1\}} \Pi (x,\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c), &{} \text {if} \; (c,c') \in \hat{{\underline{M}}} \times \hat{{\underline{M}}}'\\ \phi _{\tau }(c'|c), &{} \text {otherwise},\\ \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

meaning \(\tau '\) best-responds in the stage game for all message combinations in \(\hat{{\underline{M}}}\times \hat{{\underline{M}}}'\), and reacts identical to \(\tau \) otherwise. It follows that since \(\lambda _{L}(\hat{{\underline{M}}}) \lambda _{L}(\hat{{\underline{M}}}') > 0\), \( \lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} V_{\tau '}(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) - V_{\tau }(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) > 0, \) which contradicts \(\tau \) being stable.

Now, suppose instead for all \((c,c') \in {\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\), we have \(\Pi (1, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c) = \Pi (0, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c)\), meaning actions h and d yield the same payoff in expectation. The anti-coordination nature of the stage game then implies that \(f(c,{\underline{s}}) > \Pi (0, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c) = \Pi (1, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c)\). Let \(\Pi _{\tau }(c) :=\Pi (0, \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)|c)\). Now, consider a type \(\tau '\) with \(\phi _{\tau '}(c|c') = 1\) and \(\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) = 0\) for all \((c,c') \in {\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\), and \(\phi _{\tau '} = \phi _{\tau }\) otherwise. Given some \((c,c') \in {\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\), a type \(\tau '\) receives an expected fitness payoff of \(\Pi _{\tau '}(c) \ge \epsilon \cdot f(c,{\underline{s}}) + (1-\epsilon ) \Pi _{\tau }(c) > \Pi _{\tau }(c)\), noting that in an interaction with another \(\tau '\) they receive at least \(f(c,{\underline{s}})\), and if interacting with a type \(\tau \), they obtain \(\Pi _{\tau }(c)\) in expectation. Since the set \({\hat{M}}\times {\hat{M}}'\) is assumed to have positive measure and payoffs are equal for message combinations outside of the set, this implies as in the previous case that \( \lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} V_{\tau '}(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) - V_{\tau }(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) > 0 \), contradicting the stability of \(\tau \). \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 2

Sufficiency: Let \(L \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) be the lottery chosen by a type \(\tau \) and a type \(\tau '\). Let \(\phi _{\tau }(c'|c) \in \{0,1\}\) and \(\phi _{\tau }(c|c') = 1- \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)\) for almost all \(c, c' \in M\). Suppose there is a set \({\hat{M}} \times \hat{M'} \subset M \times M\) with positive measure (according to L) such that \(\phi _{\tau '}(c|c') \in (0,1)\). For any c, this yields an expected fitness payoff in the stage game for a type \(\tau '\) of:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \Pi _{\tau '}^{\epsilon }(c)&:=\epsilon \cdot \bigl [ \phi _{\tau '}(c|c') \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)\bigr ) f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c|c')\bigr ) \phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) f(c,{\underline{s}}) \\&\quad +\bigl (\phi _{\tau '}(c|c')\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) + (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c|c'))(1-\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)) \bigr )f(c,0) \bigr ]\\&\quad + (1-\epsilon ) \cdot \bigl [ \phi _{\tau '}(c|c') \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)\bigr ) f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c|c')\bigr ) \phi _{\tau }(c'|c) f(c,{\underline{s}})\\&\quad \bigl (\phi _{\tau '}(c|c')\phi _{\tau }(c'|c) + (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c|c'))(1-\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)) \bigr )f(c,0) \bigr ]. \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$

A type \(\tau \) obtains:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \Pi _{\tau }^{\epsilon }(c)&:=\epsilon \cdot \bigl [ \phi _{\tau }(c|c') \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)\bigr ) f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau }(c|c')\bigr ) \phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) f(c,{\underline{s}})\\&\quad \times \bigl (\phi _{\tau }(c|c')\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) + (1-\phi _{\tau }(c|c'))(1-\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)) \bigr )f(c,0) \bigr ]\\&\quad + (1-\epsilon ) \cdot \bigl [ \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)\bigr ) f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + \phi _{\tau }(c'|c)f(c,{\underline{s}})\bigr ], \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$

where we made use of the fact that \(\phi _{\tau }(c'|c) = 1- \phi _{\tau }(c|c')\). Since \(\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) \in (0,1)\) and \(f(c,{\underline{s}}) > f(c,0)\), we have \(\lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} \Pi _{\tau }^{\epsilon }(c) > \lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} \Pi _{\tau '}^{\epsilon }(c)\). Note further that this extends to \(\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) \in [0,1]\), which given that strategies are non-identical would imply \(\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) = 1-\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)\), which leads to an allocation of 0 social good in any such pairing. As both types are assumed to choose the same L, this applies to all \(c \in {\hat{M}}\) and we can conclude that \(\lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} V_{\tau }(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) - V_{\tau '}(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon )>0\), as required.

Necessity: This follows directly from the proof of Lemma 1. \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 3

Take a population configuration \((\tau , \tau ', \epsilon )\) and suppose the resident types preferences over lotteries are such that they choose the trivial lottery in every equilibrium. Consider a sequence of lotteries \(\{L_n\}_{n=1}^{\infty }\) with each \(L_n\) such that there is a probability mass of \(\frac{1}{2n+1}\) at \(-\delta \), and a probability mass of \(1-\frac{1}{2n+1}\) distributed uniformly over the interval \([0, \frac{\delta }{n}]\), with \(\delta < c_0\). Note that every such \(L_n\) is a fair and bounded lottery. It follows from Lemma 2 that if a type \(\tau \) is stable, then if there are distinct messages, we have \(1- \phi _{\tau '}(c'|c) \in \{0,1\}\) and \(\phi _{\tau }(c|c') = 1- \phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)\). Suppose \(\tau \) follows such a strategy.

Given the population configuration and lottery choices, the fitness payoff of a type \(\tau \) in any equilibrium is bounded above by

$$\begin{aligned} f_{\tau }(\epsilon ) :=(1-\epsilon ) f\bigl (c_0, s_0\bigr ) + \epsilon f\bigl (c_0, {{\overline{s}}}\bigr ), \end{aligned}$$

where \(s_0 :=\frac{{{\overline{s}}}{\underline{s}}}{{{\overline{s}}}+{\underline{s}}}\), i.e. the expected interior Nash equilibrium payoff, and we made use of Jensen’s inequality, noting that \(f(c_0, s_0) \ge {{\,\mathrm{{\mathbb {E}}}\,}}[f(c_0, S(a_i, a_j)) | p_{\text {NE}}(a_i,a_j)]\) for a f weakly concave in s, with \(p_{\text {NE}}(a_i,a_j)\) the Nash equilibrium probability distribution over action combinations.

The expected fitness of a type \(\tau '\) choosing a lottery \(L^n\) and stage game strategy \(\phi _{\tau '} = \phi _{\tau }\) is bounded below by:

$$\begin{aligned} f_{\tau '}^n(\epsilon ) :=\left( 1-\frac{1}{2n}\right) f\bigl (c_0, {\underline{s}}\bigr ) \end{aligned}$$

where we set the fitness of all types with consumption outcomes \(c < c_0\) to 0. Note that \(s_0 < {\underline{s}}\) and hence \(f(c_0,{\underline{s}}) > f(c_0,s_0)\). We can conclude that:

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0}\lim _{n \rightarrow \infty } f_{\tau }(\epsilon ) - f_{\tau '}^n(\epsilon ) < 0. \end{aligned}$$

It follows from continuity that we can find \(n^*\) and \(\epsilon ^*\) such that for every \(n>n^*\) and every \(\epsilon <\epsilon ^*\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} V_{\tau '}(\tau ,\tau ',\epsilon ) \ge f_{\tau '}^n(\epsilon ) > f_{\tau }(\epsilon ) \ge V_{\tau }(\tau ,\tau ',\epsilon ) \end{aligned}$$

in some equilibrium if \(L^n \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \). The result follows. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 1

Take a configuration \((\tau , \tau ', \epsilon )\). It follows from Lemma 1 that if (i) is violated, \(\tau \) cannot be stable. Suppose now (i) holds and there is an equilibrium in which type \(\tau \) chooses a lottery L and \(\tau '\) chooses a lottery \({\hat{L}} \ne L\), \(\; {\hat{L}} \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \), while \(\phi _{\tau } = \phi _{\tau '}\). Let \({{\overline{M}}}_L(c_0)\) be the smallest interval that contains \(M_L(c_0)\).

Case \(c_0 \in M_L(c_0)\): Condition (ii) implies that \(\int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _L(c-c_0) dc = F_{\tau }(c_0|G)\). Furthermore, (ii) and (iii) together imply that

$$\begin{aligned} \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{{\hat{L}}}(c-c_0) dc \le F_{\tau }(c_0|G) = \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{L}(c-c_0) dc. \end{aligned}$$

Any such lottery\(\; {\hat{L}}\) yields weakly lower expected fitness than L and hence \(V_{\tau }(\tau , \tau ',\epsilon ) \ge V_{\tau '}(\tau , \tau ',\epsilon )\).

Case \(c_0 \notin M_L(c_0)\): Take any \(c^* \notin M_L(c_0)\) but \(c^* \in {{\overline{M}}}_L(c_0)\). As any L must be fair, there exist \(c_1, c_2, c_3 \in M_L(c_0)\) such that \(c_1< c^*< c_2 < c_3\). Suppose \(F_{\tau }(c^*) > \alpha F_{\tau }(c_3) + (1-\alpha ) F_{\tau }(c_1)\), with \(\alpha = \frac{c^* - c_1}{c_3 - c_1}\). Note that the right-hand side corresponds to the expected (fitness) outcome of an individual with consumption \(c^*\) that chooses a (fair) lottery \(L_{\alpha } \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) that yields \(c_3- c^*\) with probability \(\alpha = \frac{c_3 - c^*}{c_3 - c_1}\) and \(c_1\) with \(1-\alpha \).

Now, consider a lottery \(L_{\beta }\) that yields \(c_3 - c_2\) with probability \(\beta = \frac{c_2 - c_1}{c_3 - c_1}\) and \(c_1 - c_2\) with \(1-\beta \). Clearly, \(L_{\beta }\) is also fair and bounded and hence in \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \). It follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \int F(c|G)\lambda _{L_{\beta }}(c-c_2) dc = \beta F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\beta ) F_{\tau }(c_1|G) = F_{\tau }(c_2|G) \end{aligned}$$

where the last equality follows from (ii), noting that \(M_{L_{\beta }}(c_2) = \{c_1, c_3\} \subset M_L(c_0)\). Consider another lottery \(L_{\gamma }\) that yields \(c_3 - c_2\) with probability \(\gamma = \frac{c_3 - c_2}{c_3-c^*}\) and \(c^* - c_2\) with \(1-\gamma \). This is again a fair and bounded lottery. By construction:

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\gamma ) F_{\tau }(c^*|G) >\gamma F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\gamma )\bigl [\alpha F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\alpha ) F_{\tau }(c_1|G)\bigr ] \end{aligned}$$

But then

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \gamma F_{\tau }(c_3) + (1-\gamma ) F_{\tau }(c^*|G) >&\; \bigl (\gamma + (1-\gamma )\alpha \bigr ) F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\gamma )(1-\alpha ) F_{\tau }(c_1|G)\bigr )\\ =&\; \beta F_{\tau }(c_3|G) + (1-\beta ) F_{\tau }(c_1|G), \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$

This contradicts (iii). It follows that for any \(c^*\) in \({{\overline{M}}}_{L}(c_0)\), we have \(F_{\tau }(c^*|G) \le \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{L^*}(c-c^*) dc\), for any \(L^* \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) such that \(M_{L^*}(c^*) \subseteq M_L(c_0)\). Furthermore, this holds with equality for any \(c^* \in M_L(c_0)\). It then follows that \(\int F(c|G) \lambda _{L}(c-c_0) dc \ge \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{L'}(c-c_0) dc\) for any \(L' \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) with \(M_{L'}(c_0) \subseteq M_{L}(c_0)\). It follows directly from (iii) that this inequality also holds for an arbitrary \({\hat{L}} \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \).

The final step is to show that a departure from a strategy \(\phi _{\tau }\) that efficiently correlates actions cannot lead to higher expected fitness if the lottery choice of the resident satisfies (ii) and (iii). If \(\phi _{\tau '}\) differs from \(\phi _{\tau }\) for a measurable set of message combinations in an equilibrium with an aggregate distribution G, then as \(\epsilon \rightarrow 0\), \(F_{\tau '}(c|G)\) approaches

$$\begin{aligned} F_{\tau '}(c|G) \!=\! \int \Bigl ( \phi _{\tau '}(x|c)(1-\phi _{\tau }(c|x))\cdot f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + (1-\phi _{\tau '}(x|c))(\phi _{\tau }(c|x))\cdot f(c,{\underline{s}}) \Bigr ) dG(x). \end{aligned}$$

Using the same argument as in the proof of Lemma 2, we can conclude that \(\lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} F_{\tau '}(c|G) - F_{\tau }(c|G) \le 0\) for all \(c \in M_G\), with the inequality strict for any c where \(\phi _{\tau '}(c'|c)\) differs from \(\phi _{\tau }(c'|c)\) for a set of messages with positive measure according to G. Combining this with the previous argument, we can further conclude that for any \({\hat{L}} \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \), as \(\epsilon \rightarrow 0\), we have:

$$\begin{aligned} \int F_{\tau '}(c|G) \lambda _{{\hat{L}}}(c-c_0) dc < \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{{\hat{L}}}(c-c_0) dc \le \int F_{\tau }(c|G) \lambda _{L}(c-c_0) dc \end{aligned}$$

with L the lottery choice of \(\tau \) in equilibrium. Accordingly, \(\lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} V_{\tau '}(\tau ,\tau ',\epsilon ) - V_{\tau }(\tau ,\tau ',\epsilon ) < 0\). The result follows. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

Let \(v: {\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits }_+ \times [0,1] \rightarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits }_+\) be a Bernoulli utility function over consumption and rank defined as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} v(c,r) :=r \cdot f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + (1-r) \cdot f(c,{\underline{s}}). \end{aligned}$$
(5)

Suppose preferences over lotteries in \(\mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \), given an aggregate consumption distribution G and a consumption endowment c, can be represented as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} V(L \; | \; c, G) = \int v\bigl (c+x,r_G(c+x)\bigr ) \lambda _{L}(x-c) dx, \end{aligned}$$
(6)

where \(r_G(x)\) captures the measure of individuals with consumption below x (or a convex combination between the measure of individuals strictly and weakly below x in the case of a mass point at x), defined as

$$\begin{aligned} r_G(x) :={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} G(x), &{} \text {if } \lambda _G(x) = 0\\ \alpha {\underline{G}}(x) + (1-\alpha ) G(x), &{} \text {otherwise}, \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

for some \(\alpha \in (0,1)\) and \({\underline{G}}(x)\) the left-limit of G(x). \(V(L \; | \; c, G)\) amounts to the expected utility from consumption and consumption rank outcomes under lottery L, given G and c. It follows from the proof of Lemma 3 that a lottery choice from the set of all fair and bounded lotteries that maximizes (6) cannot result in a mass point at any \(c>0\) for a pure population in any equilibrium.

Consider the following strategy in the stage game:

$$\begin{aligned} \phi (c'|c) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if } c > c',\\ 0, &{} \text {if } c < c',\\ \frac{f(c,{{\overline{s}}})- f(c,0)}{f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + f(c,{\underline{s}}) - 2 f(c,0)}, &{} \text {otherwise}. \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

There exist preferences in the stage game, conditional on c and \(c'\), that admit this as a unique equilibrium strategy (i.e. Table 5). It follows from Lemma 2 that a type with such preferences is evolutionarily stable against any other type that has the same choice behaviour over lotteries. The remaining question is whether V leads to equilibrium choices over lotteries that are neutrally stable.

Given Assumptions 1 and 2, v is continuous and strictly concave in c. This means conditions of Proposition 1 (i) of Ray and Robson [34] are satisfied. This result implies the existence of a unique equilibrium distribution over messages G in a pure population with a corresponding lottery choice \(L \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \) that is among the maximizers of (5). Furthermore, in any equilibrium, \(v(c,r_G(c))\) is linear over the support of G and strictly concave elsewhere. By construction, for a continuous G,

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} F_{\tau }(c|G) =&\int \phi _{\tau }(x|c) f(x,{{\overline{s}}}) dG(x) + \int \bigl (1-\phi _{\tau }(x|c)\bigr ) f(x,{\underline{s}}) dG(x)\\ =&r_G(c) f(c,{{\overline{s}}}) + (1-r_G(c)) f(c,{\underline{s}}). \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Hence, in any equilibrium, \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) is linear in c over the support of G and strictly concave elsewhere. Conditions (i)-(iii) of Proposition 2 are satisfied. Such preferences are neutrally stable. \(\square \)

Additional Result: Necessity of Linearity

The following result shows that stable preferences must be such that they induce a lottery choice and stage game strategy in equilibrium that render \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) linear and strictly increasing over the support of the consumption distribution G. This implies that condition (ii) of Proposition 1 is a necessary condition. And furthermore, while roles in the stage game do not have to be hierarchical in the sense that higher consumption yields a higher allocation of s, expected fitness does need to be strictly increasing in consumption (given the expected allocation of s for each consumption level).

Result 1

A type \(\tau \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {T}}}}\limits \) is neutrally stable only if for any equilibrium of the pure population with a consumption distribution G, \(\; F_{\tau }(c|G)\) is strictly increasing and linear in c, for almost all c in the support of G.

Proof

Let \(L_{\tau }\) be the lottery choice corresponding to such a G. Suppose not and there is an interval \(I \subset {{\,\textrm{supp}\,}}(L_{\tau })\) such that \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) is weakly decreasing in m over I and strictly increasing elsewhere. Note that for a stability, \(L_{\tau }\) needs to be continuous. Then for almost all \(c \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathbb {R}}}}\limits _+\), \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) is bounded below by \(f(c,{\underline{s}})\), which is strictly concave in c. This implies that \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) can only be weakly decreasing over a bounded interval. Let \({{\overline{c}}} \equiv \sup I\), which by the previous argument must exist. Then for almost all \(c \in I\), any fair gamble \((1-\alpha ) (c-\epsilon ) + \alpha {{\overline{c}}}+\epsilon \) must deliver expected fitness strictly greater \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) for an arbitrarily small \(\epsilon \) and the \(\alpha \in (0,1)\) that makes the lottery fair. Let \({\hat{L}}\) be such a lottery.

Then, there exists a mutant type \(\tau '\), with preferences such that \({\hat{V}}({\hat{L}}|c,G) > {\hat{V}}(L|c,G)\), for all \(L \in \mathop {\mathrm {{\mathscr {L}}}}\limits \), with \(L \ne {\hat{L}}\). It follows that for such a \(\tau '\), we have \( \lim _{\epsilon \rightarrow 0} V_{\tau '}(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) - V_{\tau }(\tau , \tau ', \epsilon ) > 0, \) which contradicts \(\tau \) being stable. It can be easily verified that the same is true if \(F_{\tau }(c|G)\) is increasing but strictly convex over an interval I. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Staab, M. Evolution of Risk-Taking Behaviour and Status Preferences in Anti-coordination Games. Dyn Games Appl 13, 1320–1342 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-023-00537-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-023-00537-4

Keywords

Navigation