Log in

Vilfredo Pareto’s Sociologia in relation to Adam Smith’s the theory of moral sentiments

  • Research Article
  • Published:
International Review of Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is abundantly clear that Vilfredo Pareto held Adam Smith in high regard for his contributions to political economy, yet, in his Trattato di Sociologia Generale, there is no mention of Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments. This study presents a comparison of these two great studies of sentiment, utility and action. It is established that there is a basic compatibility between Pareto’s conception of non-logical action in the Sociologia and Smith’s distinction in the TMS between regular and irregular sentiments, yet the two thinkers investigated these conceptions and distinctions from very different, sometimes inconsistent, perspectives. We also offer some reasons why there has been considerable debate over an alleged inconsistency between Smith’s political economy and his philosophical study of sentiments, but no such similar debate in relation to Pareto’s political economy and his sociological study of sentiments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (France)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Athol Fitzgibbons has noted, the figure of the impartial spectator may come about first from an external agent to the individual, such as the guardian of a child, growing over time into a tribunal within each one’s breast when decisions affecting other people are to be made (Fitzgibbons 2003:63–65). McLure and Arthmar (2023:221–224) also discuss the relationship between Smith’s impartial spectator and Pareto’s Sociologia.

  2. Pareto used the term derivations to indicate all kinds of explanations combining events in an imaginary chain of causes and conceived by human beings to justify their non-logical actions. “The usual purpose of a derivation, in fact, is to satisfy with pseudo-logic the need of logic, of thinking, that the human being feels” (Pareto, Sociologia 1916, § 975 [1935:592]).

  3. The phrase «the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people» was coined by Francis Hutcheson (Fleischacker 2020).

  4. This explains why Hollander (2016) compares Smith with Hutcheson and Hume when making the case for regarding the first one as a develo** an ‘ethical utilitarianism’ in TMS.

  5. There is also “a fairly standard view among philosophers that [the] TMS is a book in the utilitarian tradition.” (Witztum and Young 2013:573).

  6. Amos Witztum, Jeffrey T. Young (2013:600) also reject the contention that Smith is utilitarian, although they do so because ‘happiness’ does not feature as a motivator of human actions and moral judgements.

  7. As a selfish passion, a prudent act of self-interest falls between acts of the social passions and the unsocial passions and, as such, it “is never either so graceful as is sometimes the one set, nor is ever so odious as is sometimes the other” (Smith, TMS 1759, I, ii,v,§ 1, [1976:40]).

  8. Sentiments are not, of course, rational per se, but Smithian action under the influence of sentiments need not be ‘rational’ because the agent does not necessarily act to maximise utility due to the influence of propriety. Witztum and Young made a similar point when they observed that Smith “does not view human beings as rational in the modern sense and as motivated to maximise something called ‘utility’” (2013:575).

  9. “[E]vil which is done without design should be regarded as a misfortune to the doer as well as to the sufferer.” (Smith, TMS 1759, II.iii.III.§ 3, [1976:106]) and, as such, a “man of humanity, who accidentally, and without the smallest degree of blameable negligence, has been the cause of the death of another man, feels himself piacular, though not guilty” (Smith, TMS 1759, II.iii.III.§ 3, [1976:107]). For a discussion of Smith’s position on ‘blame’ when harm resulting from action is not due to ill will or culpable ignorance, see Hankins (2016). See also Schliesser (2017:121–136), for a very detailed analysis of Smith’s account of the piacular feeling; and Paganelli and Simon (2022:277), for an overview of the main points raised in the secondary literature on that subject.

  10. Pareto offers the following examples of genus 4α non-logical actions: the creation of the Greek language and the policy actions of King William I to promote the welfare and greatness of Prussia (Sociologia, 1916 § 151 [1935:84, 87]). Perhaps it should also be noted that Pareto’s genus 3α non-logical actions concern the situation where the objective end of an action would be accepted if the agent knew what it was. However, actions classified within genus 3, as well as actions that fall within genus 1, have no subjective purpose and, in Pareto’s view, “are of scant importance to the human race” (Pareto, Sociologia 1916, § 154 [1935:79]). For that reason, genera 1 and 3 actions are not considered in this essay.

  11. We thank Paul Oslington for raising this point.

  12. A precursor in the use of marginal utility in social analysis, Hermann H. Gossen, in Entwickelung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs, und der daraus fliessenden Regeln für menschliche Handeln (translated as The Laws of Human Relations and the Rules of Human Action Derived Therefrom, 1983), published in 1854, also criticized monopolies and any restriction of commerce. Pareto (1895) appears to have implicitly drawn on Chap. 3 (A criticism of absolute value) of Gossen’s book when criticising Francesco Ferrara and Domenico Berardi for confusing absolute value with relative value when considering the subjective approaches to value theory.

References

  • Aspers P (2001) Crossing the Boundary of Economics and Sociology: the case of Vilfredo Pareto. Am J Econ Sociol 60(2):519–545

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1780) An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. T. Payne and Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Borgatta G (1924) I rapporti tra la Sociologia e La Scienza Economica Nell’Opera Paretiana. Giornale Degli Economisti E Rivista Di Statistica 65:81–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziel P, Higgins J (2006) Pareto, Parsons and the boundary between Economics and Sociology. Am J Econ Sociol 65(1):109–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgibbons A (2003) Adam Smith’s system of Liberty, Wealth, and Virtue. Orford University, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleischacker S (2020) Adam Smith’s Moral and Political Philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/smith-moral-political/, accessed 18 September 2023

  • Gossen HH, ([1854] (1983) The laws of human relations and the rules of Human Action Derived Therefrom. M.I.T, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankins K (2016) Adam Smith’s Intriguing Solution to the Problem of Moral Luck. Ethics 126(3):711–746

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollander S (2016) Ethical utilitarianism and ‘The theory of Moral sentiments’: Adam Smith in Relation to Hume and Bentham. East Econ J 42(4):557–580

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livingston A (1935) Footnote 14 in V pareto, the mind and society, vol 1. Harcourt, Brace and Company, New York, p 12

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchionatti R, Mornati F (2021) Pareto’s Trattato Di Sociologia Generale: a behaviourist ante Litteram Approach. Camb J Econ 45(2):353–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLure M (2001) Pareto’s mechanical analogy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • McLure M (2007) The Paretian School and Italian fiscal sociology. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLure M (2022) Pareto on Classical Political Economy: ‘Per La Verità’. Pensiero Economico Italiano 30(2):99–115

    Google Scholar 

  • McLure M, Arthmar R (2023) Sentiment, Action, and Utility: Vilfredo Pareto’s Sociologia in Relation to Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments, in Atti dei Convegni Lincei 356, Convegno Vilfredo Pareto a Cento Anni dalla Scomparsa, Roma, 15–16 maggio 2023, Roma, Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei: 207–231

  • Montes L (2003) Das Adam Smith Problem: its origins, the stages of the current debate, and one implication for our current understanding of Sympathy. J History Economic Thought 25(1):63–90

  • Paganelli MP (2008) The Adam Smith Problem in Reverse: self-interest in the wealth of nations and the theory of Moral sentiments. Hist Polit Econ 40(2):365–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paganelli MP, Simon F (2022) Crime and punishment: Adam Smith’s theory of Sentimental Law and Economics. J History Economic Thought 44(2):268–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V (1895) Per La Verità. Giornale Degli Economisti 11(6):423–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V (1901) –02 Les Systèmes Socialistes. Paris: Giard et Briére, Italian trans. I Sistemi Socialisti 1974 Torino: Unione Tipografico-Editrice Torinese

  • Pareto V (1906) Manuale di Economia Politica. Milan: Società Editrice Libraria, revised and translated into French as Manuel d’économie politique 1909 Paris: Giard et Briére; and the Italian and French editions translated into English as, Manual of Political Economy: A Critical and Variorum Edition 2014 edited by A. Montesano, A. Zanni, L. Bruni, J. S. Chipman, M. McLure, Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Pareto V (1916) Trattato Di Sociologia Generale. Florence: Barbara, English translation (1935), the mind and society. Harcourt, Brace and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V (1971) Cours d’Économie Politique. Lausanne: Rouge, Italian trans. Corso Di Economia Politica. Unione Tipographico-Editrice Torinese, Torino, pp 1896–1897

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayre-McCord G (2010) Sentiments and spectators: Adam Smith’s theory of Moral Judgement. The Adam Smith Review, volume 5: essays commemorating the 250th anniversary of the theory of Moral sentiments. Routledge, London, pp 124–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser E (2017) Adam Smith: systematic philosopher and public thinker. Oxford University, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (ed) ([1759] 1984) The theory of Moral sentiments. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis

  • Smith A, ([1776] (1981) An Inquiry into the Nature and causes of the Wealth of nations. Liberty Classics, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Tajima K (2007) The theory of institutions and collective action in Adam Smith’s theory of Moral sentiments. J Socio-Econ 36:578–594

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarascio VJ (1968) Pareto’s Methodological Approach to Economics. University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill

    Google Scholar 

  • Witztum A (2008) Smith’s theory of actions and the Moral significance of Unintended consequences. Eur J History Economic Thought 15(3):401–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witztum A, Young JT (2013) Utilitarianism and the role of utility in Adam Smith. Eur J History Economic Thought 20(4):572–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

MM wrote the initial draft. RA reviewed and revised the initial draft. MM then visited RA at the University of Buckingham where they discussed the document and agreed on the final version of the paper. Both authors reviewed the submitted manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael McLure.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article is a truncated version of “Sentiment, Action, and Utility: Vilfredo Pareto’s Sociologia in Relation to Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments” from the proceedings of the conference Vilfredo Pareto A Cento Anni della Scomparsa convened by the Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei in Rome on 15–16 May 2023. The authors thank Maria Pia Paganelli and Paul Oslington for their comments on the draft prepared for the abovementioned conference.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McLure, M., Arthmar, R. Vilfredo Pareto’s Sociologia in relation to Adam Smith’s the theory of moral sentiments. Int Rev Econ (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-024-00461-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-024-00461-y

Keywords

JE codes

Navigation