Log in

Mental Privacy, Cognitive Liberty, and Hog-tying

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

As the science and technology of the brain and mind develop, so do the ways in which brains and minds may be surveilled and manipulated. Some cognitive libertarians worry that these developments undermine cognitive liberty or “freedom of thought.” I argue that protecting an individual’s cognitive liberty undermines others’ ability to use their own cognitive liberty. Given that the threatening devices and processes are not relevantly different from ordinary and frequent intrusions upon one’s brain and mind, strong protections of cognitive liberty may proscribe neurotechnological intrusions but also ordinary intrusions. Thus, the cognitive libertarian position “hog-ties” others’ use of their own liberties. This problem for the cognitive libertarian is the same problem that ordinary libertarianism faces in protecting individual rights to property and person. But the libertarian strategies for resolving the problem don’t work for the cognitive libertarian. I conclude that the right to mental privacy is weaker than what cognitive libertarians want it to be.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Muñoz, et al. (2023) for a thorough framework for thinking about neurorights and freedom of the will.

  2. The most obvious threats to cognitive liberty are the coercive type, just as the most obvious threats to individual liberty are coercive. But another way in which cognitive liberty might be threatened is when one voluntarily uses invasive neurotechnologies. Thanks to anonymous reviewers for suggesting this point. I don’t address this issue here, but the analogy to the ordinary right to privacy might still be instructive. When a person handcuffs themselves to their bed, are they undermining their own individual liberty? Presumably not, which suggests that similar voluntary use of neurotechnologies fails to undermine cognitive liberty.

  3. For additional examples of those advancing the arguments in support of mental privacy and cognitive liberty, see Bublitz 2014, 2016, 2019; Bublitz and Merkel 2014; Ienca and Andorno 2017; McCarthy-Jones 2019; Paulo and Bublitz 2019

  4. This may include new drugs, or drugs that are commonly used for other reasons, but using them for cognitive enhancement would be off-label.

  5. See, for example, the aforementioned studies and especially Doris (2002) for a detailed argument regarding the implications of this work for moral psychology.

  6. I use the analogy to one’s property simply because those are terms that libertarians use and interact with. It is not to suggest that one’s home is perfectly analogous to one’s mind. There are features of one’s mind that may not be applicable to one’s property, namely that one’s mind seems more constitutive of the self and one’s property does not. See the above section on neurotechnological interventions and identity for why appealing to the relation between one’s mind and the self will not help solve the de-lum** problem for the cognitive libertarian.

References

  • Bell, V. (n.d.). A history of media technology scares, from the printing press to Facebook. Retrieved April 22, 2021, from https://slate.com/technology/2010/02/a-history-of-media-technology-scares-from-the-printing-press-to-facebook.html

  • Berg, J., J. Dickhaut, and K. McCabe. 1995. Trust, reciprocity, and social history. Games and Economic Behavior 10(1): 122–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S., and H. Gintis. 2011. A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton University Press.

  • Bublitz, C. 2016. Moral enhancement and mental freedom. Journal of Applied Philosophy 33(1): 88–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (2014). Freedom of thought in the age of neuroscience: a plea and a proposal for the renaissance of a forgotten fundamental right. ARSP: Archiv Für Rechts-Und Sozialphilosophie/Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 1–25.

  • ———. 2019. Saving the world through sacrificing liberties? A critique of some normative arguments in unfit for the future. Neuroethics 12(1): 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz, J.C., and R. Merkel. 2014. Crimes against minds: On mental manipulations, harms and a human right to mental self-determination. Criminal Law and Philosophy 8(1): 51–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2013. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(03): 181–204.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, P. 2019. Compulsory moral bioenhancement should be covert. Bioethics 33(1): 112–121

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Moral enhancement can kill. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 43(5): 568–584.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, P. (2021). Moral enhancement and the public good. Routledge.

  • DeGrazia, D. 2005. Human identity and bioethics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J.M. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge University Press.

  • Douglas, T. 2008. Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25(3): 228–245.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Entwistle, J.W., D.H. Drake, K.N. Fenton, et al. 2022. Normothermic regional perfusion: Ethical issues in thoracic organ donation. Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery 164(1): 147–154.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R.A. 1979. Nuisance law: Corrective justice and its utilitarian constraints. The Journal of Legal Studies 8(1): 49–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farahany, N.A. 2023. The battle for your brain: Defending the right to think freely in the age of neurotechnology. St. Martin’s Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and U. Fischbacher. 2004a. Social norms and human cooperation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(4): 185–190.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004b. Third-party punishment and social norms. Evolution and Human Behavior 25(2): 63–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and S. Gächter. 2000. Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. American Economic Review 90(4): 980–994.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, P., J.I. Krueger, T. Greitemeyer, et al. 2011. The bystander-effect: A meta-analytic review on bystander intervention in dangerous and non-dangerous emergencies. Psychological Bulletin 137(4): 517–537.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J.D. 2008. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Moral psychology, Vol 3: The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development, edited by W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 35–80. MIT Press.

  • Greene, J. D., F.A. Cushman, L.E. Stewart, K. Lowenberg, L.E. Nystrom, and J.D. Cohen. 2009. Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111(3): 364–371.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Güth, W., R. Schmittberger, and B. Schwarze. 1982. An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 3(4): 367–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, T., M. Olkkonen, S. Walter, and K.R. Gegenfurtner. 2006. Memory modulates color appearance. Nature Neuroscience 9(11): 1367–1368.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2011. Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics 25(2): 102–111.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. 2013. The predictive mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. 2008. Ethical intuitionism. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ienca, M., and R. Andorno. 2017. Towards new human rights in the age of neuroscience and neurotechnology. Life Sciences, Society and Policy 13(1).

  • Isen, A.M., and P.F. Levin. 1972. Effect of feeling good on hel**: Cookies and kindness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21(3): 384–388.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, S. 2000. On writing: A memoir of the craft. Simon and Schuster.

  • Krag, E. 2023. Identification with change: Narrative identity, enhancements and transformative experience. Philosophia 51(4): 2151–2170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, S., M. Kleiman-Weiner, L. Schulz, J. Tenenbaum, and F. Cushman. 2020. The logic of universalization guides moral judgment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 117(42): 26158 LP – 26169.

  • Ligthart, S., G. Meynen, and T. Douglas. (2022). Persuasive technologies and the right to mental liberty: The “smart” rehabilitation of criminal offenders. The Cambridge handbook of information technology, life sciences and human rights.

  • Mack, E. 2015. Elbow room for rights. Oxford studies in political philosophy 1(1): 194–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, K.E., and L.K. Canon. 1975. Environmental noise level as a determinant of hel** behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 32(4): 571–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy-Jones, S. 2019. The autonomous mind: The right to freedom of thought in the twenty-first century. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence 2: 19.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, S. 2009. Obedience to authority: An experimental view. HarperCollins.

  • Muñoz, J.M. 2023. Achieving cognitive liberty. Science 379(6637): 1097.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Muñoz, J.M., J. Bernácer, and F. Güell. 2023. A conceptual framework to safeguard the neuroright to personal autonomy. Neuroethics 16(3): 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. 2013. Anarchy, state, and utopia. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L.A. 2014. Transformative experience. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paulo, N., and C. Bublitz. 2019. Introduction: Political implications of moral enhancement. Neuroethics 12(1): 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I., and J. Savulescu. 2008. The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to enhance the moral character of humanity. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25(3): 162–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Unfit for the future: The need for moral enhancement. Oxford University Press.

  • Pugh, J., H. Maslen, and J. Savulescu. 2017. Deep brain stimulation, authenticity and value. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26(4): 640–657.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, J., J. Tan, T. Aziz, and R.J. Park. 2018. The moral obligation to prioritize research into deep brain stimulation over brain lesioning procedures for severe enduring anorexia nervosa. In Frontiers in Psychiatry 9: 523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryberg, J. 2017. Neuroscience, mind reading and mental privacy. Res Publica 23(2): 197–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sententia, W. 2004. Neuroethical considerations: Cognitive liberty and converging technologies for improving human cognition. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1013(1): 221–228.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 2008. Framing moral intuitions. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, D. 2012. Backing away from Libertarian self-ownership. Ethics 123(1): 32–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. 2013. Cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophy Compass 8(7): 646–663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211(4481).

  • Zimbardo, P. 2007. The Lucifer effect: Understanding how good people turn evil. Random House Publishing Group.

Download references

Funding

Not applicable

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to P. Crutchfield.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

Not applicable

Competing Interests

I have no conflicts of interest or commitment involved in the production of this work.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Crutchfield, P. Mental Privacy, Cognitive Liberty, and Hog-tying. Bioethical Inquiry (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-024-10344-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-024-10344-0

Keywords

Navigation