Log in

Less is More: A Normative Evaluation of the ECtHR’s Protection of Commercial Speech

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Academics and legal practitioners unanimously agree that two of the main justifications for protecting free speech are autonomy and democracy. Free speech contributes to both the self-development of individuals, as well as to robust democratic processes, and should therefore be protected. This is also the position of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). However, the explicit endorsement of both justifications might give rise to normative questions regarding its protection of commercial speech. While the Court has acknowledged that commercial speech does not contribute significantly to self-development nor democracy, it still awards that form of speech a relatively high level of protection. Moreover, a compelling case can be made suggesting that some forms of commercial speech, such as commercial advertising, might even harm those values. This argument is investigated closely to demonstrate an internal contradiction within ECtHR jurisprudence, between its rhetoric focused on respecting autonomy and democracy, and its practice that might in reality undermine these values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Germany)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On corporate speech: Greenwood, ‘Essential speech’; Greenwood, ‘First amendment imperialism’; Coates, ‘Corporate speech and the first amendment’; Stoll, ‘Corporate rights to free speech?’; Schauer, ‘First amendment opportunism’. On commercial speech: Weiland, ‘Expanding the periphery and threatening the core’; Piety, ‘Against freedom of commercial expression’; Piety, Brandishing the First Amendment; Sullivan and Gunther, Constitutional law.

  2. Emberland (2006).

  3. Handyside v. UK, No. 5493/72 (Court of Justice of the European Union 7 December 1976); Lingens v. Austria, No. 9815/82 (European Court of Human Rights 8 July 1986); Sener v. Turkey, No. 1676/13 (European Court of Human Rights 24 September 2019); Thoma v. Luxemburg, No. 38432/97 (European Court of Human Rights 29 March 2001); Dichand and Others v. Austria, No. 29271/95 (European Court of Human Rights 26 February 2002).

  4. E.g. Greenawalt (1989, pp. 119–155), Brison (1998, pp. 312–339), Scordato and Monopoli (2002, pp. 185–206), and Barendt (2007).

  5. Retail, Wholesale and Department Store Union v. Dolphin Delivery, 1986(2) RCS 573, 583 (Supreme Court of Canada 1986); South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence, 1999(4) SA 469, para. 67 (South African Constitutional Court 1999); Animal Defenders International vs. The United Kingdom, No. 48876/08 (European Court of Human Rights 22 April 2013); Partidul Comunistilor (Nepeceristi) v Romania (European Court of Human Rights 2007); Republican Party of Russia v. Russia (European Court of Human Rights 2015); Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. (U.S. Supreme Court 24 May 1976).

  6. Alongside other arguments such as discovery of truth—in the US context: the marketplace of ideas—and the ‘safety valve function’ of freedom of speech, which draws attention to the role of free speech in the promotion of social stability and tolerance.

  7. One notable exception to this view is Sartori (1987, pp. 315–320).

  8. For example: Dahl, Democracy and its critics, 91; For a historical overview of theories built on this assumption: Lakoff, ‘Autonomy and liberal democracy’, 394.

  9. This position has been defended, for example, by Moore (2019, pp. 620–641).

  10. Christman (2020).

  11. Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. at 770.

  12. Sneddon (2001, 15–28).

  13. Taylor (1992, p. 14) and Taylor (1985, p. 16).

  14. Taylor, Sources of the self, 68; Taylor, ‘Self-Interpreting Animals’, 35–38.

  15. Sneddon, ‘Advertising and deep autonomy’, 21.

  16. Marks (1996, pp. 209–238) and Mowbray (2014).

  17. Handyside v. UK at 49.

  18. For example: Lingens v. Austria paragraph 41; Sener v. Turkey paragraph 39; Thoma v. Luxemburg paragraph 43; Dichand and Others v. Austria paragraph 37.

  19. Barthold v. Germany, No. 8734/79 (European Court of Human Rights 25 March 1985); X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden, No. Application No. 7805/77 (European Court of Human Rights 5 May 1979); Hertel v. Switzerland, No. 59/1997/843/1049 (European Court of Human Rights 25 August 1998); Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland, No. 16354/06 (European Court of Human Rights 13 July 2012).

  20. Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beermann v. Germany, No. 10572/83 (European Court of Human Rights 20 November 1989); Hertel v. Switzerland paragraph 47; Schweizerische Radio- Und Fernsehgesellschaft Srg v. Switzerland, No. 34124/06 (ECtHR 21 June 2012).

  21. Barthold v. Germany.

  22. This becomes particularly interesting in the context of contemporary advertising, which sees a trend towards ‘brand activism', where corporations align their brands with certain values and take public stances on socio-political issues, blurring the lines between commercial and political speech for free speech jurisprudence.

  23. Sunday Times v. The United Kingdom, No. 6538/74 (European Court of Human Right 26 April 1979).

  24. Sunday Times v. The United Kingdom; Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beermann v. Germany; Groppera Radio AG and Others v. Switzerland, No. 10890/84 (European Court of Human Rights 28 March 1990); Autronic AG v. Switzerland, No. 12726/87 (European Court of Human Rights 22 May 1990); X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden.

  25. Council of Europe, European Convention on Human Rights Article 10(2): ‘The exercise of these freedoms, since it carries with it duties and responsibilities, may be subject to such formalities, conditions, restrictions or penalties as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society, in the interests of national security, territorial integrity or public safety, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, for the protection of the reputation or rights of others, for preventing the disclosure of information received in confidence, or for maintaining the authority and impartiality of the judiciary'.

  26. Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland paragraph 63.

  27. The Court has consistently granted States a wider margin of appreciation in the areas of protection of morals and religious sensitivities, see for example: Wingrove v. The United Kingdom (European Court of Human Rights 25 November 1996); Giniewski v. France (European Court of Human Rights 31 April 2006).

  28. Sunday Times v. The United Kingdom, which involved discussion of matters of public interest; TV Vest As and Rogaland Pensjonistparti v. Norway, in which the political nature of the advertisements that were prohibited called for strict scrutiny on restrictions.

  29. X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden.

  30. X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden.

  31. Piety, Brandishing the first amendment; Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland paragraph 62.

  32. Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland paragraph 7.

  33. Casado Coca v. Spain, No. 15450/89 (European Court of Human Rights 24 February 1994).

  34. Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland paragraph 62.

  35. Shiner (2003, chap. Introduction).

  36. Shiner, Introduction.

  37. Munro (2003, p. 138).

  38. X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden at 73.

  39. Munro, ‘The value of commercial speech’, 141.

  40. For example, the commercial speech at hand in Barthold v. Germany or Hertel v. Switzerland.

  41. For example, the commercial speech at hand in Casado Coca v. Spain.

  42. Barthold v. Germany.

  43. Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beermann v. Germany paragraph 32; Hertel v. Switzerland paragraph 47; Schweizerische Radio- Und Fernsehgesellschaft Srg v. Switzerland paragraph 13.

  44. Corporate speech refers to expressions made by corporations and can be either political or commercial speech. Not all forms of commercial speech are corporate speech (see for example, Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beermann v. Germany, which considered bulletins critiquing the commercial practices of large companies as commercial speech), and not all corporate speech is commercial speech (see for example Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, which concerned corporate political speech).

  45. Citizens United, a non-profit organization, contested a federal statute that imposed restrictions on autonomous corporate financial contributions towards political campaigns. In essence, this statute prohibited corporations from spending money on political campaigns (even without being directly involved in the campaign). In the case of Citizens United, this consisted in broadcasting a movie in which Hillary Clinton was portrayed as unfit for presidency. Citizens United claimed that this statute infringed on its free speech rights under the First Amendment. The Supreme Court ruled that suppressing political speech based on a speaker’s corporate identity violates the First Amendment.

  46. In Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, the Court allowed a ‘closely held' for-profit corporation to be exempt from regulations that its owners religiously object to, thus recognizing a for-profit corporation’s claim of religious freedom. The Affordable Care Act (ACA), which covers certain contraceptives, like Plan B and certain IUDs, was seen as violating the religious freedom of Hobby Lobby, an arts-and-crafts store held by a Christian family.

  47. Addo (1999, p. 187 at p. 188).

  48. See Grear (2006, pp. 171–199), Grear (2007, pp. 511–543), Petersen (2021, pp. 179–197), and Schauer (1982, chaps 4–5).

  49. Piety, Brandishing the first amendment.

  50. Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission at 46.

  51. Tucker (2010, p. 538).

  52. For readers who wish to know more about the concept of the fictional shareholder, I refer to Greenwood (1996).

  53. Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, No. 13–354; 13–356 (United States Supreme Court 30 June 2014).

  54. Burwell v. Hobby Lobby at 4.

  55. Rosenberg (2016).

  56. Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, Dissenting opinion of Judge Stevens (referring to the American Law Institute’s Principles of Corporate Governance), ‘[A] corporation… should have as its objective the conduct of business activities with a view to enhancing corporate profit and shareholder gain'.

  57. Rosenberg, ‘The Corporate Paradox of Citizens United and Hobby Lobby’, n. 18: ‘Any other goal of corporate political spending would appear highly suspicious. Without a clear profit motive, it could easily be seen as an act of self-interest by management (possibly seeking personal political favors). Further, since the subject is itself so controversial, it cannot fit neatly into the category of goodwill that justifies much real corporate philanthrophy'.

  58. Brief for American Independent Business Alliance as Amicus Curiae 11: ‘the corporation must engage the electoral process with the aim to enhance the profitability of the company, no matter how persuasive the arguments for a broader or conflicting set of priorities'.

  59. Naturally, considerations related to listener autonomy and democratic principles should still be taken into account, which will be done in the following paragraphs.

  60. See notes 54, 55, and 56.

  61. The ECtHR’s understanding of autonomy as more than a mere naked right against the state, but rather as a human capacity for self-realization is clear from its focus on autonomy as self-fulfillment and self-development in cases such as Lingens v. Austria paragraph 41: ‘[F]reedom of expression... constitutes one of the essential […] conditions for […] each individual’s self-fulfilment'; Handyside v. UK paragraph 49: ‘Freedom of expression constitutes one of the essential foundations of [a democratic] society, one of the basic conditions for its progress and for the development of every man'.

  62. Weiland, ‘Expanding the periphery and threatening the core’.

  63. The ECtHR’s understanding of autonomy as more than a mere naked right against the state, but rather as a human capacity for self-realization is clear from its focus on autonomy as self-fulfillment and self-development in cases such as Lingens v. Austria paragraph 41: ‘[F]reedom of expression... constitutes one of the essential […] conditions for […] each individual’s self-fulfilment'; Handyside v. UK paragraph 49: ‘Freedom of expression constitutes one of the essential foundations of [a democratic] society, one of the basic conditions for its progress and for the development of every man'.

  64. Barendt, Freedom of Speech, p. 15.

  65. Sneddon, ‘Advertising and deep autonomy’.

  66. Craig, ‘Living in world we’d like to live In: Capitalist utopias in an age of counterfactuality’ on how capitalist utopias sketched in advertising are made to fit a neoliberal paradigm; Budinsky and Bryant, ‘“It’s not easy being green”' on the transformation of political action and social justice in consumerist behavioral patterns; Meyers, Neoliberalism and the media; Gill and Kanai, ‘Affirmative advertising and the mediated feeling rules of neoliberalism’ on how neoliberalism focusses on gender, race, and disability as individual characteristics rather than ties to particular communities of identity or affiliation.

  67. Carrigan et al. (2004, pp. 401–417), Freestone and McGoldrick (2007, pp. 651–673), Harrison et al. (eds) (2005), Starr (2009, pp. 916–925).

  68. Carrier (2008), Maniates (2001, pp. 31–52), Smith (1998), Szasz (2007), Thompson (2011, pp. 139–144).

  69. Budinsky and Bryant ‘“It’s not easy being green”’, Cock (2011), Lubbers (2002), Kahn (2009, pp. 47–57) and Kassiola (2015).

  70. Karliner (1997) and Parguel and Guillaume (2021).

  71. Pickard, ‘The great evasion’, p. 154: (‘Because public goods are non-rivalrous (one person’s consumption does not detract from another’s) and non-excludable (difficult to monetize and to exclude from free riders), they differ from other commodities, like cars or clothes, within a capitalistic economy').

  72. Hamilton (2006), p. 8. (‘A person can consume a public good without paying for it, since it may be difficult or impossible to exclude any person from consumption').

  73. Napoli (2018, p. 90).

  74. Pickard, ‘The great evasion’, p. 155. (‘The inadequacy of commercial support for democracy-sustaining infrastructures suggests what should be obvious by now: the systematic underproduction of vital communications like journalistic media').

  75. See for example, Randall (2012, pp. 183–280). (‘Owing to the lack of direct profit motive and its pronounced public goods characteristics, speech from independent sources, like political speech, is more easily chilled than commercial speech. Economic approaches focusing on the regulation of speech account for this difference and support a higher level of protection for speech on matters of public concern than for commercial speech').

  76. Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. note 24.: (‘[…] commercial speech may be more durable than other kinds. Since advertising is the sine qua non of commercial profits, there is little likelihood of its being chilled by proper regulation and forgone entirely').

  77. Moore (2016, p. 29).

  78. The EU’s Digital Services Act is certainly a step in the right direction of regulating social media platforms, with regulations of certain types of targeted ads, increased transparency measures, etc. However, the estimated 230 new workers that will be hired to enforce the new laws are argued to be hardly sufficient compared to the vast resources available to the tech giants. Regulation of tech giants has been proven difficult to enforce in the past as well, as with the EU’s General Data Protection Regulation (G.D.P.R.), see: Satariano (2020, sec. Technology), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/04/27/technology/GDPR-privacy-law-europe.html.

  79. Ghosh and Scott (2018), Napoli (2019, pp. 203–272), Van Dijk (1998, pp. 1–384), Bucher (2018).

  80. GrrlScientist (2012).

  81. Dougherty and Isaac (2015, sec. Technology), https://www.nytimes.com/2015/11/05/technology/airbnb-and-uber-mobilize-vast-user-base-to-sway-policy.html.

  82. Fuchs (2021).

  83. Sneddon ‘Advertising and deep autonomy’, p. 18; Harry Frankfurt describes freedom as being ‘free to will what he wants to will, or to have the will he wants', or ‘securing the conformity of his will to his second-order volitions' (Frankfurt, ‘Freedom of the will and the concept of a person’, p. 15).

  84. Frankfurt, ‘Freedom of the will and the concept of a person’.

  85. Mill (1863, chap. 2).

  86. Christman (1991, pp. 1–24).

  87. Aylsworth (2020).

  88. Preston (1996, pp. 13–20).

  89. Calvert (2008, p. 205).

  90. Belk (1985, pp. 394–398).

  91. Lee et al. (2007, pp. 199–204), Ulman et al. (2015, pp. 1271–1284).

  92. Griner et al. (2021), https://www.adweek.com/agencies/the-25-best-ads-of-2021/.

  93. Oliver (1979, pp. 8–27), Lee (2014, pp. 219–239), and Yang (2019, pp. 151–165).

  94. Belk, ‘Materialism: Trait aspects of living in the material world’; Preston, The Great American Blow-Up; Lee, Broderick, and Chamberlain, ‘What Is “Neuromarketing”?’; Calvert, ‘Children as consumers’; Ulman, Cakar, and Yildiz, ‘Ethical Issues in Neuromarketing’.

  95. Stoll et al. (2008, pp. 342–359).

  96. Hubert and Kenning (2008, pp. 272–292).

  97. Pluta-Olearnik and Szulga (2022, pp. 87–104).

  98. Pluta-Olearnik and Szulga.

  99. Pluta-Olearnik and Szulga.

  100. Noggle (1996, pp. 43–55), Hanson and Kysar (1999, pp. 630–749), and Danciu (2014, pp. 19–34).

References

  • Addo, Michael K., ed. 1999. The corporation as a victim of human rights violations. In Human rights standards and the responsibility of transnational corporations. The Hague ; Boston: Kluwer Law International.

  • Animal Defenders International vs. The United Kingdom, No. 48876/08 (European Court of Human Rights 22 April 2013).

  • Autronic AG v. Switzerland, No. 12726/87 (European Court of Human Rights 22 May 1990).

  • Aylsworth, Timothy. 2020. Autonomy and manipulation: Refining the argument against persuasive advertising. Journal of Business Ethics 175: 689–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barendt, Eric. 2007. Freedom of speech, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barthold v. Germany, No. 8734/79 (European Court of Human Rights 25 March 1985).

  • Belk, Russell W. 1985. Materialism: Trait aspects of living in the material world. Journal of Consumer Research 12: 265–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brison, Susan J. 1998. The autonomy defense of free speech. Ethics 108 (2): 312–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bucher, Taina. 2018. If...then: Algorithmic power and politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Budinsky, Jennifer, and Susan Bryant. 2013. ‘It’s not easy being green': The greenwashing of environmental discourses in advertising. Canadian Journal of Communication 38 (2): 207–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, No. 13-354; 13-356 (United States Supreme Court 30 June 2014).

  • Calvert, Sandra L. 2008. Children as consumers: Advertising and marketing. The Future of Children 18 (1): 205–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, James G. 2008. Think locally, act globally: The political economy of ethical consumption. In Hidden hands in the market: Ethnographies of fair trade, ethical consumption, and corporate social responsibility, ed. Geert de Neve, 1. ed. Research in Economic Anthropology, vol. 28. Bingley: Emerald.

  • Carrigan, Marylyn, Isabelle Szmigin, and Joanne Wright. 2004. Shop** for a better world? An interpretive study of the potential for ethical consumption within the older market. Journal of Consumer Marketing 21 (6): 401–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casado Coca v. Spain, No. 15450/89 (European Court of Human Rights 24 February 1994).

  • Christman, J. 1991. Autonomy and personal history. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2020. Autonomy in moral and political philosophy. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, No. 08–205 (Supreme Court of the United States 21 January 2010).

  • Coates, John C. 2015 Corporate speech and the first amendment: History, data, and implications.

  • Cock, Jacklyn. 2011. “Green capitalism” or environmental justice? File. Helen Suzman Foundation. https://hsf.org.za/publications/focus/focus-63/Jacklyn%20Cock.pdf/view.

  • Council of Europe. 1950. European Convention on Human Rights. London: Council of Europe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, Robert L. 2012. Living in world we’d like to live in: Capitalist utopias in an age of counterfactuality. In Utopian images and narratives in advertising: Dreams for sale, ed. Luigi Daniele Manca, Alessandra Manca, and Gail W. Pieper. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, Robert A. 1991. Democracy and its critics. Reissue. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danciu, Victor. 2014. Manipulative marketing: Persuasion and manipulation of the consumer through advertising. Theoretical and Applied Economics XXI, 2 (591): 19–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dichand and Others v. Austria, No. 29271/95 (European Court of Human Rights 26 February 2002).

  • Dougherty, Conor, and Mike Isaac. 2015 Airbnb and Uber mobilize vast user base to sway policy. The New York Times, sec. Technology. https://www.nytimes.com/2015/11/05/technology/airbnb-and-uber-mobilize-vast-user-base-to-sway-policy.html.

  • Emberland, Marius. 2006. The human rights of companies: Exploring the structure of ECHR protection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freestone, Oliver, and Peter McGoldrick. 2007. Ethical positioning and political marketing: The ethical awareness and concerns of UK voters. Journal of Marketing Management 23: 651–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Christian. 2021. The digital commons and the digital public sphere: How to advance digital democracy today. Westminster Papers in Communication and Culture 16 (1): 9–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghosh, Dipayan, and Ben Scott. 2018. #digitaldeceit: The technologies behind precision propaganda on the internet. Cambridge: Harvard Kennedy School, Shorenstein Center on Media, Politics and Public Policy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, Rosalind, and Akane Kanai. 2019. Affirmative advertising and the mediated feeling rules of neoliberalism. In Neoliberalism and the media, ed. Marian Meyers. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giniewski v. France (European Court of Human Rights 31 April 2006).

  • Grear, Anna. 2006. Human rights—human bodies? Some reflections on corporate human rights distortion, the legal subject, embodiment and human rights theory. Law and Critique 17 (2): 171–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grear, Anna. 2007. Challenging corporate ‘humanity’: Legal disembodiment, embodiment and human rights. Human Rights Law Review 7 (3): 511–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, Kent. 1989. Free speech justifications. Columbia Law Review 89 (1): 119–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, Daniel. (1996) Fictional shareholders: For whom are corporate managers trustees, Revisited’ 69.

  • Greenwood, Daniel J. H. 1998 1997. Essential speech: Why corporate speech is not free. Iowa Law Review 83(5): 995–1070

  • Greenwood, Daniel J. H. 1999. First amendment imperialism. Utah Law Review, pp. 659–60.

  • Griner, David, Shannon Miller, and Stephen Lepitak 2021. The 25 best ads of 2021. Adweek, 6 December. https://www.adweek.com/agencies/the-25-best-ads-of-2021/.

  • Groppera Radio AG and Others v. Switzerland, No. 10890/84 (European Court of Human Rights 28 March 1990).

  • GrrlScientist 2012. Defend our freedom to share (or Why SOPA Is a Bad Idea). The Guardian, 19 January, sec. Science. https://www.theguardian.com/science/grrlscientist/2012/jan/19/sopa-internet

  • Hamilton, James T. 2006 All the news that’s fit to sell how the market transforms information into news. 4. Print., and First paperback print. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press.

  • Handyside v. UK, No. 5493/72 (Court of Justice of the European Union 7 December 1976).

  • Hanson, Jon D., and Douglas A. Kysar. 1999. Taking behavioralism seriously: The problem of market manipulation. New York University Law Review 74 (3): 630–749.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, Rob, Terry Newholm, and Deirdre Shaw, eds. 2005. The ethical consumer. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

  • Hertel v. Switzerland, No. 59/1997/843/1049 (European Court of Human Rights 25 August 1998).

  • Hubert, Mirja, and Peter Kenning. 2008. A current overview of consumer neuroscience. Journal of Consumer Behaviour 7 (4–5): 272–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, Richard. 2009. Producing crisis: Green consumerism as an ecopedagogical issue. In Critical pedagogies of consumption: Living and learning in the shadow of the shopocalypse, ed. Jennifer A. Sandlin and Peter McLaren, 47–57. New York: Routledge.

  • Karliner, Joshua. 1997. The corporate planet: Ecology and politics in the age of globalization. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kassiola, Joel Jay. 2015. Explorations in environmental political theory: Thinking about what we value. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, Sanford. 1990. Autonomy and liberal democracy. The Review of Politics 52 (3): 378–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Sang Yeal. 2014. When do consumers believe puffery claims? The moderating role of brand familiarity and repetition. Journal of Promotion Management 20 (2): 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Nick, Amanda J. Broderick, and Laura Chamberlain. 2007. What is ‘neuromarketing'? A discussion and agenda for future research. International Journal of Psychophysiology: Official Journal of the International Organization of Psychophysiology 63 (2): 199–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lingens v. Austria, No. 9815/82 (European Court of Human Rights 8 July 1986).

  • Lubbers, Eveline, ed. 2002. Battling big business: Countering greenwash, infiltration, and other forms of corporate bullying. Monroe, ME: Common Courage Press.

  • Maniates, Michael F. 2001. Individualization: Plant a tree, buy a bike, save the world? Global Environmental Politics 1 (3): 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marks, Susan. 1996. The European convention on human rights and its ‘democratic society'. British Yearbook of International Law 66 (1): 209–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markt Intern Verlag GmbH and Klaus Beermann v. Germany, No. 10572/83 (European Court of Human Rights 20 November 1989).

  • Meyers, Marian, ed. 2019. Neoliberalism and the media. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1863. Utilitarianism.

  • Moore, Margaret. 2019. The moral value of collective self-determination and the ethics of secession. Journal of Social Philosophy 50 (4): 620–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Martin. 2016. Tech giants and civic power. The Policy Institute. https://apo.org.au/node/64837.

  • Mouvement Raëlien Suisse v. Switzerland, No. 16354/06 (European Court of Human Rights 13 July 2012).

  • Mowbray, Alastair. 2014. Contemporary aspects of the promotion of democracy by the European Court of Human Rights. European Public Law 20(3). https://kluwerlawonline.com/journalarticle/European+Public+Law/20.3/EURO2014032.

  • Munro, Colin R. 2003. The value of commercial speech. Cambridge Law Journal 62: 134–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napoli, Philip. 2018. What if more speech is no longer the solution? First amendment theory meets fake news and the filter bubble. Federal Communications Law Journal 70: 55–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Napoli, Philip. 2019. Notes. In Social media and the public interest, 203–272. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, Robert. 1996. Manipulative actions: A conceptual and moral analysis. American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1): 43–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, Richard L. 1979. An interpretation of the attitudinal and behavioral effects of puffery. Journal of Consumer Affairs 13 (1): 8–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parguel, Béatrice, and Johnson Guillaume. 2021. Beyond greenwashing: Addressing ‘the great illusion’ of green advertising. Revue de l’Organisation Responsable.

  • Partidul Comunistilor (Nepeceristi) v Romania (European Court of Human Rights 2007).

  • Petersen, Jennifer. 2021. How speech lost its voice: The informational turn in US free speech law. History of Humanities 6 (1): 179–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickard, Victor. The great evasion: Confronting market failure in American media policy. Critical Studies in Media Communication 31 (2014).

  • Piety, Tamara R. 2013. Brandishing the First Amendment: Commercial expression in America. 1. Paperback. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piety, Tamara R. (2008). Against freedom of commercial expression. Cardozo Law Review 29(6).

  • Pluta-Olearnik, Mirosława, and Patrycja Szulga. 2022. The importance of emotions in consumer purchase decisions: A neuromarketing approach. Marketing of Scientific and Research Organizations 44 (2): 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, Ivan L. 1996. The great American blow-up: Puffery in advertising and selling. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Randall, Maya Hertig. 2012. Human rights within a multilayered constitution: The example of freedom of expression and the WTO. Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law Online 16 (1): 183–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Republican Party of Russia v. Russia (European Court of Human Rights 2015).

  • Retail, Wholesale and Department Store Union v. Dolphin Delivery, 1986(2) RCS 573 (Supreme Court of Canada 1986).

  • Rosenberg, David. 2016. The corporate paradox of citizens united and hobby lobby. SSRN Scholarly Paper. Rochester, NY.

  • Sartori, Giovanni. 1987. Theory of democracy revisited: Part two: The classical issues, vol. 2. Chatham: CQ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Satariano, Adam 2020. Europe’s privacy law hasn’t shown its teeth, frustrating advocates. The New York Times, 27 April, sec. Technology. https://www.nytimes.com/2020/04/27/technology/GDPR-privacy-law-europe.html.

  • Schauer, Frederick. 1982. Free speech: A philosophical enquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, Frederick. 2000. First Amendment opportunism.

  • Schweizerische Radio- und Fernsehgesellschaft Srg v. Switzerland, No. 34124/06 (ECtHR 21 June 2012).

  • Scordato, Marin, and Paula A. Monopoli. 2002. Free speech rationales after September 11th: The First Amendment in post-World Trade Center America symposium: Litigation, war, and politics by other means: Part iii: Civil liberties after Sept. 11. Stanford Law & Policy Review 13 (1): 185–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sener v. Turkey, No. 1676/13 (European Court of Human Rights 24 September 2019).

  • Shiner, Roger A. 2003. Freedom of commercial expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Toby M. 1998. The myth of green marketing: Tending our goats at the edge of the apocalypse. Heritage. University of Toronto Press. https://utorontopress.com/9780802080356/the-myth-of-green-marketing.

  • Sneddon, Andrew. 2001. Advertising and deep autonomy. Journal of Business Ethics 33 (1): 15–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence, 1999(4) SA 469 (South African Constitutional Court 1999).

  • Starr, Martha. 2009. The social economics of ethical consumption: Theoretical considerations and empirical evidence. Journal of Socio-Economics 38: 916–925.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoll, Mary Lyn. 2005. Corporate rights to free speech? Journal of Business Ethics 58 (1–3): 261–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoll, Marco, Sebastian Baecke, and Peter Kenning. 2008. What they see is what they get? An fMRI-study on neural correlates of attractive packaging. Journal of Consumer Behaviour 7 (4–5): 342–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, Kathleen M., and Gerald Gunther. 2007. Constitutional law, 16th edn. New York: Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunday Times v. The United Kingdom, No. 6538/74 (European Court of Human Right 26 April 1979).

  • Szasz, Andrew. 2007. Shop** our way to safety: How we changed from protecting the environment to protecting ourselves. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • TV Vest As & Rogaland Pensjonistparti v. Norway (European Court of Human Rights 11 December 2008).

  • Taylor, Charles. 1992. Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985 Self-interpreting animals. In Human agency and language: Philosophical papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Teun A. Van Dijk. 1998. Ideology: A multidisciplinary approach, 1–384. Sage.

  • Thoma v. Luxemburg, No. 38432/97 (European Court of Human Rights 29 March 2001).

  • Thompson, Craig J. 2011. Understanding consumption as political and moral practice: Introduction to the special issue. Journal of Consumer Culture 11 (2): 139–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, Anne. 2010. Flawed assumptions: A corporate law analysis of free speech and corporate personhood in Citizens United. Case Western Reserve Law Review 61 (2): 497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulman, Yesim Isil, Tuna Cakar, and Gokcen Yildiz. 2015. Ethical issues in neuromarketing: ‘I consume, Therefore I am!' Science and Engineering Ethics 21 (5): 1271–1284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. (U.S. Supreme Court 24 May 1976).

  • Weiland, Morgan. 2017. Expanding the periphery and threatening the core: The ascendant libertarian speech tradition.

  • Wingrove v. The United Kingdom (European Court of Human Rights 25 November 1996).

  • X and Church of Scientology v. Sweden, No. Application No. 7805/77 (European Court of Human Rights 5 May 1979).

  • Yang, Defeng, Ninghui **e, and Sarena J. Su. 2019. Claiming best or better? The effect of target brand’s and competitor’s puffery on holistic and analytic thinkers. Journal of Consumer Behaviour 18 (2): 151–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Institute of Philosophy at the KU Leuven. The content is solely the responsibility of the author and does not necessarily represent the official views of the Institute.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roxan Degeyter.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The author reports no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Degeyter, R. Less is More: A Normative Evaluation of the ECtHR’s Protection of Commercial Speech. Res Publica (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-024-09665-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-024-09665-z

Keywords

Navigation