Log in

Comparability of health states

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Measuring an individual’s health states presupposes the ability to compare them. I maintain that our ability to compare quantities or magnitudes of health are severely limited. It is easier to compare values of health states, but those values are context dependent and often unreliable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

There are no data relevant to this essay.

Notes

  1. It may also be the case that no comparison is possible, because the entity, like the square root of 2 is not the sort of thing that is healthy or unhealthy.

  2. I am concerned with whether health states are generally complete, not with whether there might be a few rare cases of incomparable health states, which might be accommodated as exceptions.

  3. This is over-simplified. Pre-menopausal adult women are capable of bearing children, which is arguably a more valuable activity than any of which men are capable. So this condition needs to be relativized to reference classes. But that would rule out comparisons of activity limitations across genders or age groups.

  4. This is overly simple, because distress and pain in some circumstances are healthy and their absence pathological.

  5. The global burden of disease (GBD) studies (Salomon et al. 2012) purport to measure the level of health itself of the sequela of disease and injury, but if the arguments above are sound, the global burden of disease studies are assigning values rather than measuring health itself. The GBD studies rely on the paired comparisons made by a large sample of respondents and also purport to establish three-digit values. These are “disability weights” rather than quality weights and vary from 0 if there are no disabilities to 1 if the disability is as bad as death.

  6. The HRQoL of health is sometimes understood as a vector specifying the levels of a person’s health along the various dimensions along which health states are ranked, and what I am calling HRQoL is then called the value or utility of the health state.

  7. In the case of the paired comparisons used by the GBD, it is assumed that the more agreement there is that S is better than Sʹ, the larger the difference in the values of S and Sʹ.

  8. As a referee correctly pointed out, this is a general problem with taking averages of the traits of differing entities, like the average weight of mammals. But the generality of the problem does not lessen its seriousness here.

  9. Moreover, if one asks those with paraplegia or with dyslexia to value these health states, one might discover that they assign much larger values to paraplegia and dyslexia than do most manual laborers or white-collar workers.

  10. Moreover, by means of techniques such as the standard gamble or time tradeoffs these systems provide apparent justification for assigning ratio-scale (cardinal) and interpersonally comparable values to health states.

References

  • Allotey, P., Reidpath, D., & Kouamé, A., and Robert Cummins (2003). The DALY, context and the determinants of the severity of Disease: An exploratory comparison of paraplegia in Australia and Cameroon. Social Science & Medicine, 57, 949–958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, I. (2004). A measure of freedom. Oxford University Press.

  • Chang, R. (2002). The possibility of parity. Ethics, 112, 659–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2007). Just Health. Cambridge University Press.

  • Dolan, P. and Daniel Kahneman (2008). Interpretations of utility and their implications for the valuation of health. Economic Journal, 118, 215–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C., Nebel, J., & Zuehl, J. (2022). The case for comparability. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, M., O’Brien, B., Stoddart, G., & Torrance, G. (1997). Methods for the economics evaluation of health care programmes (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press.

  • Field, M., & Gold, M. (Eds.). (1998). Summarizing population health: Directions for the development and application of population metrics. National Academies Press.

  • Gold, M., Patrick, D., Torrance, G., Fryback, D., Hadorn, D., Kamlet, M., Daniels, N., & Weinstein, M. (1996). Identifying and valuing outcomes. Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine: Report to the U.S. Public Health Service, Panel on cost-effectiveness in health and medicine (pp. 82–134). Oxford University Press.

  • Hausman, D. (2014). Health and functional efficiency. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39, 634–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. (2015). Valuing health: Well-being, freedom, and suffering. Cambridge University Press.

  • Salomon, Joshua, T., Vos, D., Hogan, et al. (2012). Common values in assessing Health outcomes from Disease and Injury: Disability weights Measurement Study for the global burden of Disease Study 2010. Lancet, 380, 2129–2143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1759). The theory of moral sentiments Reprinted and edited by D. Raphael and A. MacFie. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976.

Download references

Funding

There is no funding for this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Daniel Hausman is the sole author.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Hausman.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

There are no competing interests.

Ethics approval

This research requires no ethics approval.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hausman, D. Comparability of health states. Philos Stud (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02061-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02061-y

Navigation