Log in

Assessing alternatives: the case of the presumptive future in Italian

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we study the distribution and interpretation of a non-temporal use of the future tense in Italian, called ‘presumptive’ or ‘epistemic’, which we label here PF. We first distinguish PF from its closest modal relatives, namely epistemic necessity/possibility/likelihood modals, as well as weak necessity modals. We then propose an account of PF in declaratives and interrogatives that treats it as a special comparative subjective likelihood modal, and test its empirical predictions. A theoretical lesson drawn from this detailed study of the semantics of PF is that semantics needs sharpened theoretical tools to be able to capture the fine-grained distinctions languages make when it comes to signaling modulated epistemic commitment to a proposition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Verbs in Italian have (i) a synthetic future that has a temporal future reading (the futuro semplice), and (ii) a periphrastic future form (the futuro anteriore), constructed with the future of the auxiliary essere ‘to be’ or avere, ‘to have’, followed by the past participle of the verb. (The auxiliary is selected by the verb for reasons that are entirely independent of the issues this paper is concerned with.) The temporal interpretation of the latter is the ‘past in the future’ interpretation, as in Alle sette avremo già mangiato ‘By 7 we will have already eaten’; the non-temporal interpretation is the PF interpretation and it is the focus of this paper. The PF interpretation becomes the only available interpretation when the future (whether future semplice or futuro anteriore) co-occurs with a non-future temporal adverb. We translate PF into English sometimes by epistemic might or must, sometimes by the adverb presumably, and sometimes by the modal would, depending on what best captures our intuition concerning its contribution. As we will see below, none of these translations captures the meaning of PF in all the cases we consider here. All instances of non-temporal future forms in the paper have been boldfaced for ease of reference.

  2. We will use the following abbreviations: 1 = first person, 2 = second person, 3= third person, m = masculine, f = feminine, sg = singular, pl = plural, fut = future, pst = past, prs = present, pp = past participle, ger = gerund, inf = infinitive, cond = conditional, subj = subjunctive, impf = imperfect tense, imp = imperative.

  3. Concerning the Italian data, unless indicated otherwise, the examples provided in the paper have been constructed by the authors. The judgments we report reflect the judgments of ten native speakers of Italian, all from Northern Italy.

  4. We assume, following Mari (2012), that the presumptive future reading is also available in sentences in which the future tense receives a future temporal interpretation, but will not argue this point here.

  5. The immediate antecedent of this paper is Ippolito and Farkas (2019). The discussion of the data in the present paper is wider and more detailed than in its predecessor. Moreover, our current account differs from our earIier one, an issue to which we come back in Sect. 3.

  6. While a reviewer found infelicitous, the judgments we collected were clear: on a scale of acceptability from 1 to 7 (with 1 being the worst and 7 being the best), seven out of the ten native speakers of Italian we consulted gave a score of 7, and the remaining three gave it a score of 5 or higher.

  7. A reviewer raises the possibility that the difference between PF and must/dovere is that, while the latter requires a salient argument (cf. Mandelkern 2018), PF is ruled out in contexts where a salient argument is given. The felicity of examples like (i) show that PF is acceptable in contexts where an argument for the assertability of the PF sentence is given.

    figure k
  8. The indirect evidence condition is met in (16) because the light in the kitchen can be taken as indirect evidence for Maria being home. In (17), the doctor’s evidence is indirect because it is reported by the patient, rather than directly witnessed.

  9. For discussion of this morphological pattern cross-linguistically, see von Fintel and Iatridou (2008).

  10. We are grateful to a reviewer for this example.

  11. The presence of the question mark for dovrebbe in ignorance signals our uncertainty concerning the judgment in this case. A large scale collection of data is needed before one can reach robust generalizations concerning this modal in Italian. Since we are interested only in distinguishing PF from dovrebbe, which can be established on the basis of (20) and (21) above, the issue of the semantics of dovrebbe is beyond the scope of this paper. For relevant discussion, see Cariani (2013) and Yalcin (2016).

  12. We are grateful to Ashwini Deo for pointing us toward treating (26) as a Lauer-style mandatory implicature. If one does not accept the existence of such implicatures, (26) would have to be treated as a presupposition.

  13. The notion of (un)settledness relevant here is the same as the subjective non-veridicality condition in Giannakidou and Mari (2017). While our account shares the notion of unsettledness with the proposal in Giannakidou and Mari (2017), it crucially differs from it in that it relies on subjective likelihood rather than universal quantification, and it distinguishes epistemic from doxastic bases. In the present account, the fact that p is not settled as far as the doxastic state of the evaluating agent is concerned is an implicature that the semantics of PF gives rise to. Note also that Farkas (2003) uses the notion of settledness, under a different name, in connection with mood distribution.

  14. We are not claiming that there always is a one-to-one map** between prosodic focus and semantic focus: if the former underdetermines the latter, then we assume that the hearer will accommodate the focus structure and presupposition that allows the PF-sentence to be congruent to the qud.

  15. Note that wide focus in Bea’s utterance is required in order to make her answer congruent to Aldo’s question. Narrow focus on any subcontituent in this utterance—for example, focus on the predicate malata only—would generate a set of alternatives of the form ‘Bea is P’ of which the question would not be a subset, thus violating the congruence requirement between questions and answers.

  16. We thank Ashwini Deo and an anonymous reviewer for leading us to think about these examples.

  17. In (i), we see that it is odd for a speaker to raise one possibility with the epistemic modal potrebbe and another using PF:

    figure ap

    We do not have an explanation for this fact except to suggest that it is a pragmatically odd move to draw attention to one possibility only to discard it immediately after and draw attention to another. Indeed, the sentence improves if the speaker has a reason to consider the Carlo alternative while believing that the Ezio alternative is the most likely:

    figure aq
  18. The judgments of our consultants varied in the doctor scenario. Six out of ten speakers rated this sentence < 5 (again, on a 1–7 scale), two speakers gave the sentence a 5, and the remaining two speakers gave the sentence a 6. Given that in our account the oddness of this example is rooted in expectations about what a doctor would say to a patient, this variation is not entirely unexpected.

  19. In addition, we noted above that the math scenario also violates the npi.

  20. Contrastive focus on the necessity modal deve is required in this situation.

  21. We thank Ashwini Deo and an anonymous reviewer for pushing us to clarify the fact that a comparative notion of subjective likelihood is needed rather than an absolute one.

  22. We are grateful to our reviewers for encouraging us to consider these cases in detail.

  23. For reasons of space we do not discuss the alternative in which the disjunction scopes over PF.

  24. Embedding PF under essere certo, ‘be certain’, and essere convinto, ‘be convinced’, was judged considerably more acceptable by our consultants than embedding PF under credere, ‘believe’, and pensare, ‘think’, and among the last two, credere was judged worse than pensare. A detailed study of these differences and their significance lies outside the scope of this paper.

  25. All of our ten linguistic consultants gave the B sentence in (66) a score \(\ge 5\) (and six of them gave the sentence a score \(\ge 6\)).

  26. For discussion of the restrictions on the embedding of non-root modals more generally (e.g. epistemic modals), see for example Papafragou (2006).

  27. This proposition is only meaningful with the “frequency” reading: Gianni is more often in his office than at home. The frequency reading is not the intended reading for (68). A second reason to doubt that the comparative phrase più che a casa is part of the prejacent is that there is a clear intonational break and a pitch change (from high to low) between it and the preceding sentence Gianni sarà in ufficio, ’Gianni is presumably in the office’, hence the comma in (68).

  28. For more on diagnosing evidentiality, see Murray (2010) and references therein.

  29. The challenge may only be appropriate if the addressee thinks that the speaker is either lying or is incapable of assessing her own feelings and thoughts (for example, in a situation where the speaker’s judgment is impaired). This is what Korotkova (2019) (based on Anand (2009)) calls performance disagreement.

  30. We saw with C’s utterance in (61) that one can challenge the prejacent itself: this is acceptable because what is challenged in this case is not the subjective assessment but only the truth of the prejacent.

  31. For discussion of ‘faultless disagreement’ see Kölbel (2003), Lasersohn (2005), Stephenson (2007), von Fintel and Gillies (2011), Korotkova (2016), among many others.

  32. If one assume that, in the context of the example, being a man or a woman exhaust the possibilities, a question like (84) will be interpreted with disjunction taking scope over PF so that the question can be felicitously paraphrased as sarà un uomo o sarà una donna?, ‘will this be a man or will this be a woman?’ Under this binary assumption, interpreting disjunction in the scope of PF would give rise to infelicity since there is only one possible disjunctive proposition that can be construed out of two possibilities.

  33. Even though the contestant is asked to think about a war and a treaty, the answer can still be considered an ‘educated guess’ in that the contestant is going to make an inference based on general facts about wars and treaties, while lacking any specific information about this particular historical event.

  34. As far as we are aware, this fact has not been noted in the previous literature. Fălăuş and Laca (2014) mention that PF is acceptable in rhetorical questions in Spanish and Romanian. This may be a genuine difference between Italian on the one hand and Spanish and Romanian on the other. On closer scrutiny, it might also turn out that rhetorical questions whose answer is presupposed to be obvious in the input context, as in (88), are not felicitous in Spanish and Romanian either. Our Italian informants uniformly rejected rhetorical questions with PF.

  35. Concessive uses of the non-temporal future have been investigated for example by Squartini (2012) and Baranzini and Mari (2019).

References

  • Abusch, D. (1997). Sequence of tense and temporal de re. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, P. (2009). Kinds of taste. Ms.,UCSC.

  • Anand, P., & Hacquard, V. (2013). Epistemics and attitudes. Semantics & Pragmatics, 6(8), 1–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baranzini, L., & Mari, A. (2019). From epistemic modality to concessivity: Alternatives and pragmatic reasoning per absurdum. Journal of Pragmatics, 142, 116–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertinetto, P. (1979). Alcune ipotesi sul nostro futuro (con alcune osservazioni su “potere” e “dovere”). Rivista di Grammatica Generativa, 1–2(4), 77–138.

  • Bybee, J., & Pagliuca, W. (1987). The evolution of future meaning. In A. Gicalone, O. Carruba, & G. Bernini (Eds.), Papers from the Seventh International Conference on Historical Linguistics (pp. 109–120). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

  • Cariani, F. (2013). Epistemic and deontic should. Thought, 2(1), 73–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cariani, F., & Santorio, P. (2018). Will done better: Selection semantics, future credence, and indeterminacy. Mind, 127(505), 129–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Condoravdi, C. (2003). Moods and modalities for will and would. Handout for a talk given at the Amsterdam Colloquium, December 2003.

  • Copley, B. (2009). The semantics of the future. Routledge.

  • Eckardt, R. (2020). Conjectural questions: The case of German verb-final wohl questions. Semantics & Pragmatics, 13(9), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckardt, R., & Beltrama, A. (2019). Evidentials and questions. In C. Piñón (Ed.), Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12 (pp. 1–35). Paris: CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç, M. (1996). Tense and modality. In S. Lappin (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 633–657). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fălăuş, A. (2014). Presumptive mood, factivity and epistemic indefinites in Romanian. Borealis Academic Publishing, 3(2), 105–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fălăuş, A., & Laca, B. (2014). Les formes de l‘incertitude. Le futur de conjecture en espagnol et le présomptif futur en roumain. Revue de Linguistique Romane, 78, 313–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. (2003). Assertion, belief and mood choice. Paper presented at ESSLI, Vienna.

  • Farkas, D. F., & Bruce, K. B. (2010). On reacting to assertions and polar questions. Journal of Semantics, 27, 81–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frana, I., & Menéndez-Benito, P. (2015). Embedding the epistemic future in italian and spanish. Poster presented at Sinn und Bedeutung 20.

  • Frana, I., & Menéndez-Benito, P. (2019). Evidence and bias. The case of the evidential future in Italian. Proceedings of SALT, 29, 727–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2013). The future of Greek and Italian: An evidential analysis. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, 17, 255–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2017). A unified analysis of the future as epistemic modality. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 36, 85–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Göbel, A. (2017). Evidentiality and undirected questions: A new account of the German discourse particle wohl. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics,24(1), 77–86.

  • Hacquard, V., & Wellwood, A. (2012). Embedding epistemic modals in English: A corpus-based study. Semantics & Pragmatics, 5(4), 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippolito, M. (2017). Constraints on the embeddability of epistemic modals. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, 21(1), 605–622.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippolito, M., & Farkas, D. F. (2019). Epistemic stance without epistemic modals: The case of the presumptive future. Proceedings of SALT, 29, 459–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irimia, M.-A. (2010). Some remarks on the evidential nature of the Romanian presumptive. In R. Bok-Bennema, B. Kampers-Manhe, & B. Hollebrandse (Eds.), Selected papers from Going Romance (pp. 125–144). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, S. (2005). Conditional truth and future reference. Journal of Semantics, 22, 231–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2003). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korotkova, N. (2016). Disagreement with evidentials: A call for subjectivity. In J. Hunter, M. Simons, & M. Stone (Eds.), The 20th Workshop on the Semantics and Pragmatics of Dialogue (pp. 65–75). New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korotkova, N. (2019). Status of the evidential requirement. Ms., University of Konstanz/University of Tübingen.

  • Kratzer, A. (2009). Modals and context-dependency. Colloquium, Harvard University, February 20.

  • Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, 643–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauer, S. (2014). Mandatory implicatures in gricean pragmatics. In J. Degen, M. Franke, and N. Goodman (Eds.), Proceedings of the Formal and Experimental Pragmatics Workshop (pp. 21–28). Tübingen.

  • Littell, P., Matthewson, L., & Peterson, T. (2009). On the semantics of conjectural questions. In M. Schenner, R.-M. Déchaine, T. Peterson, & U. Sauerland (Eds.), Evidence from evidentials (pp. 89–104). Vancouver, BC: University of British Columbia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelkern, M. (2018). What “must” adds. All Souls College: Oxford University.

  • Mari, A. (2012). On the evidential nature of the Italian future, HAL, archives-ouvertes.fr edition.

  • Mari, A. (2018). The french future: Evidentiality and incremental information. In A. Foolen, H. de Hoop, & G. Mulder (Eds.), Evidence for evidentiality (pp. 199–226). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, L., Rullmann, H., & Davis, H. (2008). Evidentials as epistemic modals: Evidence from St’át’imcets. The Linguistic Variation Yearbook, 7, 201–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mihoc, T. (2014). The Romanian future-and-presumptive auxiliary. McGill Working Papers in Linguistics 24(1) 64–80.

  • Mihoc, T., Bhadra, D., & Falaus, A. (2019). Epistemic modals, deduction, and factivity. Proceedings of SALT, 29, 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, S. (2010). Evidentiality and the structure of speech acts. Ph.D. thesis, Rutgers University.

  • Papafragou, A. (2006). Epistemic modality and truth conditions. Lingua, 116, 1688–1702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietrandrea, P. (2005). Epistemic Modality. Functional properties and the Italian system. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (1996). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. The Ohio State University Working Papers in Linguistics (OSUWPL), 49, 91–136.

  • Roberts, C. (2017). Agreeing and assessing: Epistemic modals and the question under discussion. Ms., OSU and NYU.

  • Roelofsen, F., & Farkas, D. (2015). Polarity particle responses as a window onto the interpretation of questions and assertions. Language, 91(2), 359–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1996). Focus. In S. Lappin (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 271–297). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1, 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Squartini, M. (2012). Evidentiality in interaction: The concessive use of the Italian future between grammar and discourse. Journal of Pragmatics, 44(15), 2116–2128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epsitemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(4), 691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uegaki, W., & Roelofsen, F. (2018). Do modals take propositions or sets of propositions? Evidence from Japanese darou. Proceedings of SALT, 28, 809–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(3), 221–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. (2011). Might made right. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 108–130). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2008). How to say Ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals. In J. Guéron & J. Lecarme (Eds.), Time and modality (pp. 115–141). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Winans, L. D. (2016). Inferences of ‘will’. Ph.D. thesis, UCLA.

  • Yalcin, S. (2016). Modalities of normality. In N. Charlow & M. Crisman (Eds.), Deontic modality (pp. 230–255). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michela Ippolito.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We are grateful to Ashwini Deo, the editor of this paper, and three anonymous reviewers at Linguistics and Philosophy for the extensive and helpful comments we received throughout the reviewing process. For discussions and feedback, we thank the audience at SALT 29, as well as the audiences at the Expressing Evidence workshop held at the University of Konstanz (June 2019), ModUni1 workshop held in Leiden (December 2018), and the Semantics & Pragmatics Reading Group at the University of Toronto. All mistakes are ours. The first author has been supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council Insight Grant #496697.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ippolito, M., Farkas, D.F. Assessing alternatives: the case of the presumptive future in Italian. Linguist and Philos 45, 943–984 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-021-09338-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-021-09338-7

Keywords

Navigation