Log in

Can the mind be embodied, enactive, affective, and extended?

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent years, a growing number of thinkers have begun to challenge the long-held view that the mind is neurally realized. One strand of critique comes from work on extended cognition, a second comes from research on embodied cognition, and a third comes from enactivism. I argue that theorists who embrace the claim that the mind is fully embodied and enactive cannot consistently also embrace the extended mind thesis. This is because once one takes seriously the central tenets of enactivism, it becomes implausible to suppose that life, affectivity, and sense-making can extend. According to enactivism, the entities that enact a world of meaning are autonomous, embodied agents with a concerned point of view. Such agents are spatially situated, differentiated from the environment, and intentionally directed towards things that lie at a distance. While the extended mind thesis blurs the distinction between organism and environment, the central tenets of enactivism emphasize differentiations between the two. In addition, enactivism emphasizes that minded organisms are enduring subjects of action and experience, and thus it is implausible to suppose that they transform into a new form of life whenever they become intimately coupled to some new element in their environment. The proponent of enactivism and embodied cognition should acknowledge that life and affectivity are relational and environmentally embedded, but resist the further claim that these phenomena are extended.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Germany)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Theorists such as O’Regan and Noë (2001) have articulated an alternative theory of enactivism that centers on the way in which perception rests on knowledge of sensorimotor contingencies. However, my paper focuses primarily on what some theorists have called “autopoietic” or “autonomic” enactivism.

  2. For a discussion of some of the key objections that have been raised against this account, see Thompson (2011).

  3. Some authors (e.g. Stephan et al. 2014 and Colombetti and Roberts 2015) have appealed to the parity principle to argue that affectivity can extend. In their view, some of the internal components of emotions have extrabodily functional equivalents. Although these arguments merit further consideration, here I set them aside. Because functionalism is in tension with EE, the enactivist needs to appeal to something other than the parity principle to show that affectivity extends.

  4. More might be said about the how Barbaras’ comments about distance relate to recent debates concerning the sense of agency and the sense of ownership. However, there is not sufficient space to explore this here.

References

  • Adams, A., & Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In M. Aydede & P. Robbins (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 78–95). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnellos, A., et al. (2009). Towards the naturalization of agency based on an interactivist account of autonomy. New Ideas in Psychology. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2009.09.005.

  • Baker, L. R. (2009). Persons and the extended-mind thesis. Zygon, 44(3), 642–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbaras, R. (2010). Life and exteriority: The problem of metabolism. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buhrmann, T., & Di Paolo, E. (2015). The sense of agency—A phenomenological consequence of enacting sensorimotor schemes. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-015-9446-7.

  • Clark, A. (2008a). Pressing the flesh: A tension in the study of the embodied, embedded mind? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 37–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008b). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2015). Enactive affectivity, extended. Topoi, 1–11.

  • Colombetti, G., & Roberts, T. (2015). Extending the extended mind: The case for extended affectivity. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1243–1263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester H. (2008). On corporeal prostheses as an essential human characteristic. Presented at ESPRA 2: subjectivity and the body, 29 January–1 February 2008, Copenhagen. http://espra.risc.cnrs.fr/ESPRA2Home.htm.

  • Dempsey, L., & Shani, I. (2013). Stressing the flesh: In defense of strong embodied cognition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 590–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28, 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Di Paolo, E. (2011). The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics and Cognition, 19(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

  • Hanna, R., & Maiese, M. (2009). Embodied minds in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. New York: Harper and Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Clark, A. (2009). Introduction: Mind embodied, embedded, enacted: One church or many? Topoi, 28, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maiese, M. (2015). Embodied selves and divided minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (smith, C. Trans.) London: Routledge.

  • O’Regan, J.K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1041.

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2001). Embodied cognition. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. (2014). Emotions and the extended mind. Collective emotions, 32–46.

  • Stephan, A., Walter, S., & Wilutzky, W. (2014). Emotions beyond brain and body. Philosophical Psychology, 27(1), 65–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: Extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 465–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 407–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of the mind. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(10), 418–425.

  • Thompson, E., & Stapleton, M. (2009). Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi, 28, 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, T. (2011). Reply to commentaries. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(5–6), 176–223.

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2010). Minds, things and materiality. In L. Malafouris & C. Renfrew (Eds.), The cognitive life of things: Recasting the boundaries of the mind (pp. 29–37). Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research Publications.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Julian Kiverstein and two anonymous referees for their very helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michelle Maiese.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Maiese, M. Can the mind be embodied, enactive, affective, and extended?. Phenom Cogn Sci 17, 343–361 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9510-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9510-6

Keywords

Navigation