Spacetime Relationalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Problem of Time

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 190))

  • 3610 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter further develops Background Independence and the Problem of Time at the classical level for approaches in which spacetime is primary (a position we started in Chap. 10). We consider spacetime diffeomorphisms, and contrast the corresponding Spacetime Relationalism with the dynamically primary approaches’ Temporal and Configurational Relationalism. Given that spacetime diffeomorphisms generators close, we also consider associated notions of spacetime or path (alias Bergmann) observables. We introduce the space of spacetimes and the space of general relativity solutions. Finally, we give the first of two parts of an outline of Bergmann’s work and its expansion by Pons, Salisbury and Sundermeyer. This involves using larger groups than the spacetime diffeomorphisms, such for now the diffeomorphism-induced gauge group.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One might moreover consider a notion of weak equality instead, now meaning up to terms containing the generators. Also, one is only to select subsets of generators which close algebraically. The Jacobi identity applying to all Lie brackets, these are also guaranteed to close as a Lie algebra.

  2. 2.

    Infinitesimal transformations \(\vec{X} \rightarrow \vec{\widetilde{X}}\) can be written as \(\vec{X} - \vec{\widetilde{X}} = \vec{\epsilon }\). Viewed as solutions in terms of Hamiltonian variables, the right hand side functions here are so-called descriptors: a fairly standard Gauge Theoretic notion, see e.g. [13, 134]). For GR, descriptors are of the particular form \(\vec{\upnu }(\vec{X}; \boldsymbol{\**}(\vec{X})]\). Here \(\boldsymbol{\**}\) denotes the set of dynamical fields \(\boldsymbol{\uppsi}\) and \(\mathbf{h}\); note that this specifically excludes the lapse \(\upalpha \) and shift \(\upbeta^{i}\). Dittrich’s \(\mbox{V}^{\mu }\) in (25.30) and Chap. 27.5’s Weyl scalars can be viewed as particular cases of descriptors.

  3. 3.

    See [721] for the sense in which this is ‘induced’. \(\mathit{Digg}(\mathfrak{m})\) might also be denoted \(BK(\mathfrak{m})\) after Bergmann and Komar [134], though they themselves referred to it as the ‘\(Q\)-group’. Physicists Josep Maria Pons, Donald Salisbury and Kurt Sundermeyer prefer to use the Bergmann–Komar name for the subsequent projected version of this group that introduced in Chap. 32.4. Incidentally, the existence of this larger invariance group does not by itself dictate that it is the gauge group. [This is one example of Sect. 27.7’s matter, as well as the more specific reason to use the projected version.]

  4. 4.

    For suppose that a model, with maximal symmetry group , fails to capture some physically meaningful features which themselves do not respect . Then there is a smaller choice group, ℌ, which happens to be more physical. Moreover, one way of finding it and the missing physically meaningful features is to consider not just for the original model, but rather it and all its subgroups. This is out of the possibility that one or more of these are more physically valuable than itself.

  5. 5.

    Moreover, extending \(\mathfrak{q}\) or its spacetime equivalent may further enlarge the largest symmetry group ℌ, break ℌ or both at once. I.e. extend the subgroup that survives a breaking in a different way from the original ℌ.

References

  1. Anderson, J.L.: Principles of Relativity Physics. Academic Press, New York (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bergmann, P.G.: “Gauge-invariant” variables in general relativity. Phys. Rev. 124, 274 (1961)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Bergmann, P.G., Komar, A.: The coordinate group symmetries of general relativity. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 5, 15 (1972)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Fischer, A.E.: The theory of superspace. In: Carmeli, M., Fickler, S.I., Witten, L. (eds.) Relativity, Proceedings of the Relativity Conference in the Midwest, Cincinnati, Ohio, 2–6 June 1969 Plenum, New York (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Géhéniau, J., Debever, R.: Les Quatorze Invariants de Courbure de l’Espace Riemannien a Quatre Dimensions [The 14 curvature invariants of 4-\(d\) Riemannian space]. Helv. Phys. Acta Suppl. 4, 101 (1956)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Giulini, D.: Some remarks on the notions of general covariance and background independence. In: Stamatescu, I.O. (ed.) An Assessment of Current Paradigms in the Physics of Fundamental Interactions. Lect. Notes Phys., vol. 721, p. 105 (2007). ar**v:gr-qc/0603087

    Google Scholar 

  7. Isham, C.J.: Aspects of Quantum Gravity. Lectures Given at Conference: C85–07-28.1 (Scottish Summer School 1985:0001), available on KEK archive

    Google Scholar 

  8. Isham, C.J.: Canonical quantum gravity and the problem of time. In: Ibort, L.A., Rodríguez, M.A. (eds.) Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups and Quantum Field Theories. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht (1993). gr-qc/9210011

    Google Scholar 

  9. Muga, G., Sala Mayato, R., Egusquiza, I. (eds.): Time in Quantum Mechanics, vol. 1. Springer, Berlin (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Muga, G., Sala Mayato, R., Egusquiza, I. (eds.): Time in Quantum Mechanics, vol. 2. Springer, Berlin (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Penrose, R., Rindler, W.: Spinors and Space-Time: Volume 1, Two-Spinor Calculus and Relativistic Fields. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1984)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Pons, J.M., Salisbury, D.C., Shepley, L.C.: Gauge transformations in the Lagrangian and Hamiltonian formalisms of generally covariant theories. Phys. Rev. D 55, 658 (1997). gr-qc/9612037

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Samuel, J.: Is Barbero’s Hamiltonian formulation a gauge theory of Lorentzian gravity? Class. Quantum Gravity 17, L141 (2000). gr-qc/0005095

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Stewart, J.M.: Advanced General Relativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1991)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Szekeres, P.: The gravitational compass. J. Math. Phys. 6, 1387 (1965)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Anderson, E. (2017). Spacetime Relationalism. In: The Problem of Time. Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 190. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-58848-3_27

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation