• 1201 Accesses

Abstract

A rule for the acceptance of scientific hypotheses called ‘the principle of cost-benefit dominance’ is shown to be more effective and efficient than the well-known principle of the maximization of expected (epistemic) utility. Harvey’s defense of his theory of the circulation of blood in animals is examined as a historical paradigm case of a successful defense of a scientific hypothesis and as an implicit application of the cost-benefit dominance rule advocated here. Finally, various concepts of ‘dominance’ are considered by means of which the effectiveness of our rule may be increased.

Michalos, A.C.: 1970. Cost-benefit versus expected utility acceptance rules. Theory and Decision, 1, pp. 61–88. © 1970 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (Canada)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (Canada)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (Canada)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (Canada)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    All but the last of these rules are reviewed in Michalos (1969b).

  2. 2.

    MacCrimmon (1968) and Pruzan (1966) contain less thorough comparisons of these and similar rules, with respect to different applications. Raiffa (1969) contains a defense of the Bemoulli-Bayes principle for “multi-attribute” problems. Hinrichs and Taylor (1969) and Prest and Turvey (1965) contain excellent surveys of recent work on cost-benefit analysis.

  3. 3.

    A fairly thorough analysis of decision-making costs may be found in Michalos (to be published).

  4. 4.

    These two definitions, of course, are merely special applications of the famous Pareto Principle that has been used widely by economists since Vilfredo Pareto’s Cours d'tconomie politique, 1877, e.g., Arrow (1951), Harsanyi (1955), Hildreth (1953), Luce and Raiffa (1964), Newman (1965), Rothenberg (1961), Tullock and Buchanan (1962).

  5. 5.

    ‘Effectiveness’ and ‘efficiency’ are analyzed in greater detail in Michalos (1970b).

  6. 6.

    On the problem of scales and their transformations see Ackoff (1962), Fishbum (1964), Luce and Raiffa (1964) and Rothenberg (1961).

  7. 7.

    A vast amount of literature has been produced by proponents and opponents of “pragmatic utility”, and it is doubtful that I could contribute anything novel to the discussion here. Interested readers may find critiques of the concept in Arrow (1951), Ellsberg (1961), Kuhn (1963), MacCrimmon (1968), Manheim and Hall (1968), Michalos (1965a, 1966, 1967), Rothenberg (1961) and Stedry and Chames (1966).

  8. 8.

    A more thorough analysis of the technique may be found in Miller and Starr (1960).

  9. 9.

    The path outlined here for Galen’s view has been put together from excerpts from On the Functions of Parts of the Human Body in Crombie (1959), Fleming (1955), Graubard (1964) and Singer (1957) and from the remarks of the historians themselves.

  10. 10.

    Both Crombie (1959, II, pp. 235–237) and Pagel (1961, pp. 177–182) regard these analogies as highly influential on Harvey’s thinking.

  11. 11.

    The flow of blood through capillaries was not observed until 1661 by Marcello Malpighi (Crombie 1959, II).

  12. 12.

    Crombie (1959, I, pp. 164–165) and Fleming (1955) completely missed this point, and criticized historians who had referred to a general ebbing and flowing in the whole venous system. See also section “Internal Consistency” below.

  13. 13.

    Galen imagined that the vital functions were produced by the activity of three kinds of “spirits”, namely, the “vital spirit” of the heart, the “natural spirit” of the liver and the “animal spirit” of the brain. The first “accounted for” the “vital faculty” or “principle of animal life”, the second for the “vegetative faculty” or “principle of nutrition and growth” and the third for the “psychic faculty” or “spiritual principle of life” (Crombie 1959; Ackermann 1961, pp. 163–167).

  14. 14.

    The mitral valves are located between the auricles and ventricles in the mitral orifIces on both sides of the heart. The one referred to here is on the left side and known as the ‘bicuspid valve’ because it has two flaps or doors.

  15. 15.

    According to the first quotation in section “External Analogies” above, he evidently accepted a geocentric theory of the planetary system.

  16. 16.

    Most of the case histories cited in Bunge (1961) seem to have admitted some reversals, although a more careful analysis might reveal a different picture.

  17. 17.

    From a formal or logico-mathematical point of view, voting theory and the theory of multi-attribute decision-making are virtually indistinguishable. See, for example, Mackenzie (1967), Michalos (1969c, 1970a, to be published, unpublished manuscript).

  18. 18.

    This is also suggested by MacCrimmon (1968).

References

  • Ackermann, R. (1961). Inductive simplicity. Philosophy of Science, 28, 152–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ackoff, R. L. (1962). Scientific method. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, E. J., Bourne, L. E., & Brown, F. G. (1955). Concept identification as a function of irrelevant information and instructions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 49, 153–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. F. (1957). Induction and hypothesis. Ithaca.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchdahl, G. (1969). Metaphysics and the philosophy of science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1959). Metascientific queries. Springfield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1961). The weight of simplicity in the construction and assaying of scientific theories. Philosophy of Science, 28, 120–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1967). Scientific research (Vol. II). Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burks, A. W. (1968). The pragmatic-Humean theory of probability and Lewis’ theory. In P. A. Schilpp (Eds.), The philosophy of C. I. Lewis (pp. 415–464). LaSalle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1968). Lewis’ ethics of belief. In P. A. Schilpp (Eds.), The philosophy of C. I. Lewis (pp. 223–242). LaSalle

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombie, A. C. (1959). Medieval and early modem science (Vol. I and II). Garden City.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodgson, C. L. (Lewis Carroll). (1963). A discussion of the various methods of procedure in conducting elections (reprinted in D. Black. The theory of committees and elections (pp. 214–222). Cambridge.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the savage axioms, P-2173. Santa Monica: The RAND Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishbum, P. C. (1964). Decision and value theory. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, D. (1955). Galen on the motions of the blood in the heart and lungs. Isis, 46, 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galen. (1916). On the natural faculties (A. J. Brock Trans.). London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1968). Corroboration, explanation, evolving probability, simplicity and a sharpened razor. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19, 123–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1959). Recent developments in the theory of simplicity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 19, 429–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graubard, M. (1964). Circulation and respiration. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 63, 309–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, W. (1889). An anatomical disquisition on the motion of the heart and blood in animals (Willis’s translation revised and edited by A. Bowie, London, 1889 and reprinted in C. M. B. Camac (Ed.). (1959). Classics of medicine and surgery. New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, J. R. (1962). Human data processing limits in decision making. Electronics System Division Report, ESD-TDR-62-48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1960). Inductive inconsistencies. Synthese, 12, 439–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1962). Deductive-nomological versus statistical explanation. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. III, pp. 98–169). Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Recent problems of induction. In R. G. Colodny (Ed.), Mind and cosmos (pp. 112–134). Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertz, H. (1956). The principles of mechanics. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildreth, C. (1953). Alternative conditions for social orderings. Econometrica, 21, 81–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinrichs, H. H., & Taylor, G. M. (Eds.). (1969). Program budgeting and benefit-cost analysis. Pacific Palisades, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Suppes, P. (1966). Aspects of inductive logic. Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffreys, H. (1957). Scientific inference. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. (1957). A treatise on probability. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, A. (1963). The study of society (p. 111). Homewood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1968). Changes in the problem of inductive logic. In I. Lakatos (Ed.), The problem of inductive logic. Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1968). Theories of scientific method from Plato to Mach. History of Science, 6, 1–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leach, J. (1968). Explanation and value neutrality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19, 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leinfellner, W. (1968). Generalization of classical decision theory. In L. Borch & J. Mossin (Eds.), Risk and uncertainty (pp. 196–210). London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1962). On the seriousness of mistakes. Philosophy of Science, 29, 47–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with truth. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, I. M. D. (1950). A critique of welfare economics. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D., & Raiffa, H. (1964). Games and decisions. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCrimmon, K. R. (1968). Decisionmaking among multiple-attribute alternatives: A survey and consolidated approach, memorandum RM-4823-ARPA. Santa Monica: The RAND Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, W. J. M. (1967). Free elections. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manheim, M. L., & Hall, F. L. (1968). Abstract representation of goals, P-67–24. Department of Civil Engineering, M.I.T.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margenau, H. (1950). The nature of physical reality. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, A. (1970). Science, reason and value. Theory and Decision, 2 (to be published).

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1965a). Probability and degree of confirmation: A study of the disagreement between Karl Popper and Rudolf Carnap from 1934 to 1964. Doctoral dissertation, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1965b). Two theorems of degree of confirmation. Ratio, 7, 196–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1966). Estimated utility and corroboration. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 16, 327–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1967a). Postulates of rational preference. Philosophy of Science, 34, 18–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1967b). Descriptive completeness and linguistic variance. Dialogue, 6, 224–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1969a). An alleged condition of evidential support. Mind, 78, 440–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1969b). Principles of logic. Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1969c). A theory of decision-making evaluation. Paper read at the Annual Meeting of the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1969d). Positivism versus the elermeneutic-dialectic school. Theoria, 35(Part 3), 267–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. Analytic and other “dumb” guides of life. Analysis (to be published).

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1970a). Decision-making in committees. American Philosophical Quarterly, 7, 91–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. (1970b). Efficiency and morality. Paper read at the Annual Meeting of the Western Division of the American Philosophical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. The costs of decision-making. Public Choice (to be published).

    Google Scholar 

  • Michalos, A. C. The impossibility of an ordinal measure of acceptability (unpublished manuscript).

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. A. (1956). The magical number seven, plus or minus two. Psychological Review, 63, 81–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. W., & Starr, M. K. (1960). Executive decisions and operations research. Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, J. (1960). Games against nature. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Decision processes (pp. 49–60). New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstem, O. (1947). The theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, P. (1965). The theory of exchange. Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osgood, C. S., Suci, G. J., & Tannenbaum, P. H. (1957). The measurement of meaning. Urbana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagel, W. (1961). The position of Harvey and van Helmont in the history of European thought. In R. M. Palter (Ed.), Toward modern science (Vol. II, pp. 175–191). New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prest, A. R., & Turvey, R. (1965). Cost-benefit analysis: A survey. The Economic Journal, 75, 683–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pruzan, P. M. (1966). Is cost-benefit analysis consistent with the maximization of expected utility? In J. R. Lawrence (Ed.), Operational research and the social sciences (pp. 319–336). London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa, H. (1969). Preferences for multi-attributed alternatives, memorandum RM-5868-DOT/RC. Santa Monica: The RAND Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1969). Introduction to value theory. Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothenberg, J. (1961). The measurement of social welfare. Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1966). The foundations of scientific inference. Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. (1963). Method in the physical sciences. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, R. N. (1964). On subjectively optimum selection among multi-attribute alternatives. In M. W. Shelly & G. L. Bryan (Eds.), Human judgments and optimality (pp. 257–281). New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A., & March, J. G. (1958). Organizations. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, C. (1957). A short history of anatomy and physiology from the Greeks to Harvey. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stedry, A. C., & Chames, A. (1966). The attainment of organization goals through appropriate selection of subunit goals. In J. R. Lawrence (Eds.), Operational research and the social sciences (pp. 147–164). London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1962). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkie, J. S. (1965). Harvey’s immediate debt to Aristotle and to Galen. History of Science, 4, 103–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, P. M. (1969). The structure of acceptance and its evidential basis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19, 325–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, C. Z., & Alexis, M. (1962). Basic frameworks for decisions. Journal of the Academy of Management, 5, 151–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The number of friends who have kindly given me suggestions and encouragement is almost embarrassingly large, but I would like to express my gratitude to Myles Brand, Cliff Hooker, David Hull, Scott Kleiner, Hugh Lehman, Werner Leinfellner, Andrew McLaughlin and Tom W. Settle.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alex C. Michalos .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Michalos, A.C. (2017). Cost-Benefit Versus Expected Utility Acceptance Rules. In: Connecting the Quality of Life Theory to Health, Well-being and Education. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51161-0_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51161-0_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-51160-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-51161-0

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation