A New Typology of Uncertainty (for Decision-Making)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Uncertainty in Strategic Decision Making

Abstract

Argues that all past typologies are flawed, if not wholly wrong. Explains and argues a new primary typology of uncertainty based on treatability. Explains and argues a new (supplementary) secondary typology based on the elements of the decision-making process. Describes a (supplementary) tertiary typology based on a 5W1H perspective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
GBP 19.95
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
GBP 95.50
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
GBP 119.99
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Please see this Chapter’s supplement for further details on a selection of the more important issues.

  2. 2.

    It is important to note that there is nothing that can be done with unknown unknowns: From such absolute ignorance we can derive nothing but absolute ignorance (Graaff, 1957; Stewart, 2021). This is not just theoretical, but very real—as it is observed that executives don’t know what they don’t know (Courtney et al., 2013). In terms of theory, though, the outcome of unknown unknowns—surprises—may be differentiable; for example, into those that are fully unexpected versus those that run counter to the expected outcome (Shackle, 1953).

  3. 3.

    Note that, when the unknown is (theoretically) addressable, there may still be (subjective) uncertainties about its addressability and the specific best way to address it (Hertwig et al., 2019; Kuhlthau, 1993).

  4. 4.

    There are two latent questions regarding the unknown unknowns of the top flow. However, each violates the assumption that objective reality exists and that the decision is being considered from that perspective. The first question relates to ‘knowing’ that an unknown unknown exists—e.g., being certain that the model of the problem is (substantively) incomplete. Objectively, if there is an unknown unknown then we cannot know that that factor exists and, thus, cannot act to make it exist. We could have a ‘feeling’ that something is missing, but that is purely subjective. The second question relates to a hypothetical regarding if the unknown factor was known at the time (e.g., by going back in time once it had been revealed) then could its characteristic’s value also have been known. Objectively, again, if it is an unknown unknown then that value is also unknown at the time of the decision. Subjectively, though, such a hypothetical could have resulted from an unfortunate error in model-building (a subjective oversight error) that could be critiqued ex post, with regret (given if the model would have been correct and the factor known, perhaps its characteristic’s value could have also been known, and the decision then hypothetically optimized, but it wasn’t).

  5. 5.

    The literature refers to so-called wicked problems as those plagued by several of these uncertainties—where relevant parties cannot agree on the goals, the outcome set, the probabilities and the proper valuation methods (e.g., Head, 2022). Others have characterized wickedness in other, separable ways, often dealing with specific contexts, like entrepreneurship (Arend, 2015).

  6. 6.

    Note that we have proposed a set of typologies that have not appeared in the literature (at least as formal typologies to our knowledge). This implies, and we state this now explicitly, that all previous typologies have been flawed. The flaws are many (e.g., mixing sources with types; lacking specificity; and, so on). There have been many flaws of basic logic as well. For example, several typologies fail to differentiate between gaps in a set of values of a factor (e.g., gaps in the set of possible options or outcomes) and the range of possible impacts those can values can have on a decision (e.g., Packard et al., 2017); an open set in the former sense makes much less difference than in the latter sense as to whether any real uncertainty exists (i.e., in terms of effects on the optimizability of the decision).

  7. 7.

    Recall that an unknown can arise from nature (e.g., arising in chaotic systems, and systems with evolving genotypes), or from other humans (e.g., arising from a closed ignorance—the willful non-recognition of knowledge—that can be a rational social or political choice of decision-makers), or a combination of the two (see Faber et al., 1992).

  8. 8.

    Note that Knight’s description of the role of the entrepreneur in her venture is so strong that it essentially provides a version of the ‘nexus of contracts’ theory of the firm over fifty years before it was formally proposed (Jensen & Meckling, 1976).

  9. 9.

    Further, while an entrepreneur may have superior judgment about demand uncertainty, that is no guarantee of superior judgment about the uncertainties over competition, regulation, technology, trends and so on. The uncertainty needed to provide entrepreneurial opportunities in the real world rarely entails only one dimension, yet it is treated that way in Knight (1921), making its dangers unlikely to be fully appreciated by practitioners relying on that model.

  10. 10.

    For example, the focal unknown may involve the set of possible outcome states, or the set of possible actions, or the set of possible rivals, or the payoffs of those actions in those states, or the distributions of the probabilities of the outcomes occurring, or combinations of these. Each type can entail a different approach or judgment; dealing with an incomplete set of (input) factors should differ from dealing with an unknown distribution of possible outcomes. And that is dangerous because the types can have different impacts on decisions (e.g., relating to their timing and level of commitment).

  11. 11.

    Our conclusions are made with the understanding that Knight’s is only one theory of entrepreneurial activity. Regardless, its misinterpretations don’t help the field; they impede better theorizing and better decision-making. Having a century-old model that can be so easily misinterpreted is not good for the entrepreneurship field because, if it can be dangerous to build on theoretical models like Knight’s (1921), then our lack of action on identifying and addressing its mis-interpretations inevitably means that we are likely to allow such dangerous outcomes to occur for any other theory. And, when that happens, then we really have no theory.

References

  • Abbott, J. (2005). Understanding and managing the unknown: The nature of uncertainty in planning. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 24(3), 237–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adobor, H. (2006). Optimal trust? Uncertainty as a determinant and limit to trust in inter-firm alliances. Leadership & Organization Development Journal, 27(7), 537–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aggarwal, D., & Mohanty, P. (2022). Influence of imprecise information on risk and ambiguity preferences: Experimental evidence. Managerial and Decision Economics, 43(4), 1025–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, S., Afuah, A., & Gibson, C. (2018). Editors’ comments: Should management theories take uncertainty seriously? Academy of Management Review, 43(2), 169–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arend, R. J. (2015). Wicked entrepreneurship: Defining the basics of entreponerology. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arend, R. J. (2020). Strategic decision-making under ambiguity: A new problem space and a proposed optimization approach. Business Research, 13(3), 1231–1251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, S. R., Bloom, N., & Davis, S. J. (2016). Measuring economic policy uncertainty. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 131(4), 1593–1636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bammer, G., & Smithson, M. (2008). Understanding uncertainty. Integration Insights, 7(1), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Anan, Y., Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2009). The feeling of uncertainty intensifies affective reactions. Emotion, 9(1), 123–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barney, J. B. (2002). Gaining and sustaining competitive advantage. Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, S. W., & Brownson, F. O. (1964). What price ambiguity? Or the role of ambiguity in decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 72(1), 62–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Haim, Y. (2001, June). Decision trade-offs under severe info-gap uncertainty. ISIPTA, 32–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlyne, D. E. (1960). Conflict, arousal, and curiosity. McGraw-Hill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, B. K., & Fulk, J. (1996). Executive scanning and perceived uncertainty: A multidimensional model. Journal of Management, 22(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, W. (2012). Genealogies of risk: Searching for safety, 1930s–1970s. Ecology Law Quarterly, 39, 895–987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R., & Drechsler, M. (2014). Types of uncertainty. Erkenntnis, 79, 1225–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R., & Steele, K. (2015). Making climate decisions. Philosophy Compass, 10(11), 799–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandenburger, A. M., & Nalebuff, B. J. (1996). Co-opetition. Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brod, G., Hasselhorn, M., & Bunge, S. A. (2018). When generating a prediction boosts learning: The element of surprise. Learning and Instruction, 55, 22–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S., & Postman, L. (1949). On the perception of incongruity: A paradigm. Journal of Personality, 18(2), 206–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchko, A. A. (1994). Conceptualization and measurement of environmental uncertainty: An assessment of the Miles and Snow perceived environmental uncertainty scale. The Academy of Management Journal, 37(2), 410–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. (1994). Individual decision making. In J. Kagel & A. Roth (Eds.), Handbook of experimental economics. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C., & Weber, M. (1992). Recent developments in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 325–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chawla, C., Mangaliso, M., Knipes, B., & Gauthier, J. (2012). Antecedents and implications of uncertainty in management: A historical perspective. Journal of Management History, 18(2), 200–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1977). The probable and the provable. Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M., & Jaffray, J.-Y. (1980). Rational behavior under complete ignorance. Econometrica, 48(5), 1281–1299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conrath, D. W. (1967). Organizational decision making behavior under varying conditions of uncertainty. Management Science, 13(8), B-487.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costikyan, G. (2013). Uncertainty in games. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courtney, H. (2001). 20/20 Foresight: Crafting strategy in an uncertain world. Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courtney, H. (2003). Decision‐driven scenarios for assessing four levels of uncertainty. Strategy & Leadership, 31(1), 14–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courtney, H., Lovallo, D., & Clarke, C. (2013). Deciding how to decide. Harvard Business Review, 91(11), 62–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cui, L., Wu, H., Wu, L., Kumar, A., & Tan, K. H. (2023). Investigating the relationship between digital technologies, supply chain integration and firm resilience in the context of COVID-19. Annals of Operations Research, 327(2), 825–853.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daft, R. L., & Macintosh, N. B. (1981). A tentative exploration into the amount and equivocality of information processing in organizational work units. Administrative Science Quarterly, 26(2), 207–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dattée, B., Alexy, O., & Autio, E. (2018). Maneuvering in poor visibility: How firms play the ecosystem game when uncertainty is high. Academy of Management Journal, 61(2), 466–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidsson, P. (2015). Entrepreneurial opportunities and the entrepreneurship nexus: A re-conceptualization. Journal of Business Venturing, 30(5), 674–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E., Lipman, B. L., & Rustichini, A. (1998). Recent developments in modeling unforeseen contingencies. European Economic Review, 42(3–5), 523–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech, D. (1999). Expectations and confidence under uncertainty. Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 21(3), 415–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech, D. (2003). Uncertainty and economic sociology: A preliminary discussion. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 62(3), 509–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech, D. (2011). Uncertainty: A typology and refinements of existing concepts. Journal of Economic Issues, 45(3), 621–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1915). The logic of judgements of practice. Journal of Philosophy, 12(1), 505–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimov, D. (2018). Uncertainty under entrepreneurship. In A. Fayolle, S. Ramoglou, M. Karatas-Ozkan, & K. Nicolopoulou (Eds.), Philosophical reflexivity and entrepreneurship research (pp 184–196). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimov, D. (2007a). Beyond the single-person, single-insight attribution in understanding entrepreneurial opportunities. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 31, 713–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dimov, D. (2007b). From opportunity insight to opportunity intention: The importance of person-situation learning match. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 31, 561–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dimov, D. (2016). Toward a design science of entrepreneurship. In Models of start-up thinking and action: Theoretical, empirical and pedagogical approaches (Vol. 18, pp. 1–31). Emerald Group Publishing Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dosi, G., & Egidi, M. (1991). Substantive and procedural uncertainty: An exploration of economic behaviours in changing environments. Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 1, 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downey, H. K., & Slocum, J. W. (1975). Uncertainty: Measures, research, and sources of variation. Academy of Management Journal, 18(3), 562–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downey, H. K., Hellriegel, D., & Slocum, J. W., Jr. (1975). Environmental uncertainty: The construct and its application. Administrative Science Quarterly, 20, 613–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Du, N., & Budescu, D. V. (2005). The effects of imprecise probabilities and outcomes in evaluating investment options. Management Science, 51(12), 1791–1803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, R. B. (1972). Characteristics of organizational environments and perceived environmental uncertainty. Administrative Science Quarterly, 17(3), 313–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, W. (1965). Optimal strategies for seeking information: Models for statistics, choice reaction times, and human information processing. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 2(2), 312–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn, H. J., & Hogarth, R. M. (1986). Decision making under ambiguity. Journal of Business, 59(4), S225–S250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn, H. J., & Hogarth, R. M. (1988). Decision making under ambiguity: A note. In Risk, decision and rationality (pp. 327–336). Springer Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elenkov, D. S. (1997). Strategic uncertainty and environmental scanning: The case for institutional influences on scanning behavior. Strategic Management Journal, 18(4), 287–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75(4), 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etner, J., Jeleva, M., & Tallon, J. M. (2012). Decision theory under ambiguity. Journal of Economic Surveys, 26(2), 234–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faber, M., Manstetten, R., & Proops, J. L. (1992). Humankind and the environment: An anatomy of surprise and ignorance. Environmental Values, 1(3), 217–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faulkner, P., Feduzi, A., & Runde, J. (2017). Unknowns, Black Swans and the risk/uncertainty distinction. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 41, 1279–1302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feduzi, A., Faulkner, P., Runde, J., Cabantous, L., & Loch, C. (2021, In press). Heuristic methods for updating small world representations in strategic situations of Knightian uncertainty. Academy of Management Review, 47(3), 402–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feduzi, A., Runde, J., & Zappia, C. (2012). De Finetti on the insurance of risks and uncertainties. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 329–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fontana, G., & Gerrard, B. (2004). A post Keynesian theory of decision making under uncertainty. Journal of Economic Psychology, 25(5), 619–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foss, K., Foss, N. J., & Klein, P. G. (2007). Original and derived judgment: An entrepreneurial theory of economic organization. Organization Studies, 28(12), 1893–1912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garner, W. R. (1962). Uncertainty and structure as psychological concepts. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P. (2001). Co** with ignorance: Unforeseen contingencies and non-additive uncertainty. Economic Theory, 17, 247–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D., & Muir, A. (2008). Nash equilibria with Knightian uncertainty: The case of capacities. Economic Theory, 37, 147–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graaff, J. de V. (1957). Theoretical welfare economics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant, R. M. (1996). Toward a knowledge-based theory of the firm. Strategic Management Journal, 17(S2), 109–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, M. A., & Grote, G. (2020). When is more uncertainty better? A model of uncertainty regulation and effectiveness. Academy of Management Review, 45(4), 745–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, M., MacMillan, I. C., & Thompson, J. D. (2008). Look before you leap: Market opportunity identification in emerging technology firms. Management Science, 54(9), 1652–1665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanany, E., Klibanoff, P., & Mukerji, S. (2020). Incomplete information games with ambiguity averse players. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 12(2), 135–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, L. P. (2014). Nobel lecture: Uncertainty outside and inside economic models. Journal of Political Economy, 122(5), 945–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1994). Decision theory: A brief introduction [Department of Philosophy and the History of Technology. Royal Institute of Technology. Stockholm].

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1996). Decision making under great uncertainty. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 26(3), 369–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Head, B. W. (2022). Wicked problems in public policy: Understanding and responding to complex challenges. Springer Nature.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. O. (1955). Drives and the CNS (conceptual nervous system). Psychological Review, 62, 243–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hebert, R. F., & Link, A. N. (1988). The entrepreneur: Mainstream views and radical critiques (2nd ed.). Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heiner, R. A. (1983). The origin of predictable behavior. The American Economic Review, 73(4), 560–595.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heiner, R. A. (1988). Imperfect decisions, routinized behaviour and intertial technical change. In G. Dosi, C. Freeman, R. Nelson, G. Silverberg, & L. Soete (Eds.), Technical change and economic theory. Pinter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The ‘conjunction fallacy’revisited: How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12(4), 275–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., Pleskac, T. J., & Pachur, T. (2019). Taming uncertainty. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hickson, D. J., Hinings, C. R., Lee, C. A., Schneck, R. E., & Pennings, J. M. (1971). A strategic contingencies’ theory of intraorganizational power. Administrative Science Quarterly, 16(2), 216–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hmieleski, K. M., Carr, J. C., & Baron, R. A. (2015). Integrating discovery and creation perspectives of entrepreneurial action: The relative roles of founding CEO human capital, social capital, and psychological capital in contexts of risk versus uncertainty. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 9(4), 289–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, F. O., & Hammonds, J. S. (1994). Propagation of uncertainty in risk assessments: The need to distinguish between uncertainty due to lack of knowledge and uncertainty due to variability. Risk Analysis, 14(5), 707–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth, R. M. (1980). Judgement and choice: The psychology of decision. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. H., Holyoak, K. J., Nisbett, R. E., & Thagard, P. R. (1986). Induction: Processes of inference, learning, and discovery. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, T., & Westgren, R. (2020). Carving the nature of uncertainty at its joints. Academy of Management Review, 45(4), 869–872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1950). The principles of psychology. Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, E., McGregor, I., Klackl, J., Agroskin, D., Fritsche, I., Holbrook, C., Nash, K., Proulx, T., & Quirin, M. (2014). Threat and defense: From anxiety to approach. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 219–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, J. (1972). Motives and development. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 22, 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory. Econometrica, 47, 263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapoor, R., & Adner, R. (2012). What firms make vs. what they know: How firms’ production and knowledge boundaries affect competitive advantage in the face of technological change. Organization Science, 23(5), 1227–1248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeldt, T. F. (2015). Games with exogenous uncertainty played by” Knightian” players [dev.gtcenter.org].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaur, N., & Dasgupta, C. (2018). Types of uncertainty and collaborative uncertainty management strategies evidenced during the engineering design process. In International conference on computers in education (pp. 175–180).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay, J. A., & King, M. A. (2020). Radical uncertainty. Bridge Street Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khodadad Hosseini, S. H., Hamidizadeh, M. R., Hoseini, S. M., & Lashkarboloki, M. (2011). Designing the process model of robust strategy under uncertainty. Journal of Strategic Management Studies, 2(5), 83–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. M. (1973). Competition and entrepreneurship. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, E., Daymond, J., & Paroutis, S. (2020). Design-led strategy: How to bring design thinking into the art of strategic management. California Management Review, 62(2), 30–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen, T., & Levinthal, D. A. (2007). Two faces of search: Alternative generation and alternative evaluation. Organization Science, 18, 39–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korhonen, P. J., & Wallenius, J. (2020). Different paradigms of decision-making. In Making better decisions: Balancing conflicting criteria (pp. 1–4). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhlthau, C. C. (1991). Inside the search process: Information seeking from the user’s perspective. Journal of the American Society for Information Science, 42(5), 361–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lachmann, L. M. (1976). From Mises to Shackle: An essay on Austrian economics and the kaleidic society. Journal of Economic Literature, 14(1), 54–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lampert, C. M., Kim, M., & Polidoro, F., Jr. (2020). Branching and anchoring: Complementary asset configurations in conditions of Knightian uncertainty. Academy of Management Review, 45(4), 847–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, B., & Yoo, B. (2007). What prevents electronic lemon markets? Journal of Organizational Computing and Electronic Commerce, 17(3), 217–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leiblein, M. J., Reuer, J. J., & Zenger, T. (2018). What makes a decision strategic? Strategy Science, 3(4), 558–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1982). Ignorance, probability and rational choice. Synthese, 53(3), 387–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Likierman, A. (2020). The elements of good judgment. Harvard Business Review, 98(1), 102–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipshitz, R., & Strauss, O. (1997). Co** with uncertainty: A naturalistic decision-making analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 69(2), 149–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlechild, S. (1986). Three types of market process. In R. N. Langlois (Ed.), Economics as a process: Essays in the new institutional economics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luan, S., Reb, J., & Gigerenzer, G. (2019). Ecological rationality: Fast-and-frugal heuristics for managerial decision making under uncertainty. Academy of Management Journal, 62(6), 1735–1759.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lytras, M. D., & Pouloudi, A. (2006). Towards the development of a novel taxonomy of knowledge management systems from a learning perspective: An integrated approach to learning and knowledge infrastructures. Journal of Knowledge Management, 10(6), 64–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mack, R. P. (1971). Planning on uncertainty. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacLeod, W. B., & **le, M. (2000). An experiment on the relative effects of ability, temperament and luck on search with uncertainty [University of Southern California Law School, Olin Research paper 00-12].

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, G., & Zucchella, A. (2018). Uncertainty in entrepreneurship and management studies: A systematic literature review. International Journal of Business and Management, 13(3), 98–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandel, T. F., & Wilson, I. (1993). How companies use scenarios: Practice and prescription [SRI Business Intelligence Programme Report R822].

    Google Scholar 

  • March, J. (1991). Exploration and exploitation in organizational learning. Organization Science, 2, 71–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • March, J. C., & Olsen, J. P. (1976). Ambiguity and choice in organizations. Universitetsforlaget.

    Google Scholar 

  • March, J. G., & Simon, H. A. (1958). Organizations. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • March, J. G. (1994). Primer on decision making: How decisions happen. Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markowitz, H. M. (1952). Portfolio selection. Journal of Finance, 7, 77–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCray, L. E., Oye, K. A., & Petersen, A. C. (2010). Planned adaptation in risk regulation: An initial survey of US environmental, health, and safety regulation. Technological Forecasting and Social Change, 77(6), 951–959.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullen, J. S., & Kier, A. S. (2016). Trapped by the entrepreneurial mindset: Opportunity seeking and escalation of commitment in the Mount Everest disaster. Journal of Business Venturing, 31(6), 663–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D. L., & Schaffer, M. M. (1978). Context theory of classification learning. Psychological Review, 85(3), 207–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1982). Limit pricing and entry under incomplete information: An equilibrium analysis. Econometrica, 50(2), 443–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. D. (2007). Risk and rationality in entrepreneurial processes. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 1(1–2), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. I. (Ed.). (2012). Sixty-two years of uncertainty: Historical, philosophical, and physical inquiries into the foundations of quantum mechanics (Vol. 226). Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, V. W. (1995). Organizational risk perception and reduction: A literature review. British Journal of Management, 6(2), 115–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, T. R., & James, L. R. (2001). Building better theory: Time and the specification of when things happen. Academy of Management Review, 26(4), 530–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, J. W., & Forlani, D. (2005). Missing the boat or sinking the boat: A study of new venture decision making. Journal of Business Venturing, 20(1), 47–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, D. J., & Pinelli, T. E. (1994). NASA/DOD aerospace knowledge diffusion research project [Report 30: Computer-Mediated Communication (CMC) and the communication of technical information in aerospace. Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute Report].

    Google Scholar 

  • Nosal, J. B., & Ordonez, G. (2016). Uncertainty as commitment. Journal of Monetary Economics, 80, 124–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell, R. (2013). Two post-keynesian approaches to uncertainty and irreducible uncertainty. In G. C. Harcourt & P. Kriesler (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of post-Keynesian economics (pp. 121–142). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, G. C., & Rice, M. P. (2013). A comprehensive model of uncertainty associated with radical innovation. Journal of Product Innovation Management, 30, 2–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orhnial, T. (1980). Potential surprise and portfolio theory. Diskussionsbeiträge-Serie A.

    Google Scholar 

  • Packard, M. D., & Clark, B. B. (2020). On the mitigability of uncertainty and the choice between predictive and nonpredictive strategy. Academy of Management Review, 45(4), 766–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfeffer, J., & Salancik, G. R. (1978). The external control of organizations: A resource dependence perspective. Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, S. W., Lempert, R. J., & Bankes, S. C. (2005). Sha** the future. Scientific American, 292(4), 66–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (2004). Catastrophe: Risk and response. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, K., Rosen, P., & Johnson, Ch. R. (2012). From quantification to visualization: A taxonomy of uncertainty visualization approaches. Uncertainty Quantification in Scientific Computing IFIP Advances in Information and Communication Technology, 377, 226–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa, H., & Luce, R. D. (1957). Games and decisions: Introduction and critical survey. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramoglou, S., & Tsang, E. W. (2016). A realist perspective of entrepreneurship: Opportunities as propensities. Academy of Management Review, 41(3), 410–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, C. A., & Hoogendoorn, B. (2022). The mediating role of values in the relationship between religion and entrepreneurship. Small Business Economics, 58(3), 1309–1335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rindova, V., & Courtney, H. (2020). To shape or adapt: Knowledge problems, epistemologies, and strategic postures under Knightian uncertainty. Academy of Management Review, 45(4), 787–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rock, D. (2008). SCARF: A brain-based model for collaborating with and influencing others. NeuroLeadership Journal, 1(1), 44–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouvray, D. H. (1997). The treatment of uncertainty in the sciences. Endeavour, 21(4), 154–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Runde, J. (1990). Keynesian uncertainty and the weight of arguments. Economics & Philosophy, 6(2), 275–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samsami, F., Hosseini, S. H. K., Kordnaeij, A., & Azar, A. (2015). Managing environmental uncertainty: From conceptual review to strategic management point of view. International Journal of Business and Management, 10(7), 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sargeant, S., & Yoxall, J. (2023). Psychology and spirituality: Reviewing developments in history, method and practice. Journal of Religion and Health, 62, 1159–1174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, S. M., & Cummings, L. L. (1976). Organizational environment, differentiation and perceived environmental uncertainty. Decision Sciences, 7, 447–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1996). Feelings and phenomenal experiences. In E. T. Higgins & A. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 433–465). Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle, G. L. S. (1949). Expectation in economics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle, G. L. S. (1972). Marginalism: The harvest. History of Political Economy, 4(2), 587–602.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle, G. L. S. (1979). Imagination and the nature of choice. Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, D. A., Williams, T. A., & Patzelt, H. (2015). Thinking about entrepreneurial decision making: Review and research agenda. Journal of Management, 41(1), 11–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1959). Theories of decision-making in economics and behavioral science. American Economic Review, 49, 253–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjöberg, L. (2000). Perceived risk and tampering with nature. Journal of Risk Research, 3(4), 353–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spender, J.-C. (1983). The business policy problem and industry recipes. Advances in Strategic Management, 2, 211–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stacey, R. D. (1992). Managing the unknowable: Strategic boundaries between order and chaos in organizations. Jossey-Bass Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterman, J. D. (1994). Learning in and about complex systems. System Dynamics Review, 10(2–3), 291–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, G. (2021, March). A passion for ignorance? Not knowing the half of it. AGORA Column.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sykes, H. B., & Dunham, D. (1995). Critical assumption planning: A practical tool for managing business development risk. Journal of Business Venturing, 10(6), 413–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szentkirályi, L. (2020). Luck has nothing to do with it: Prevailing uncertainty and responsibilities of due care. Ethics, Policy & Environment, 23(3), 261–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tannert, C., Elvers, H. D., & Jandrig, B. (2007). The ethics of uncertainty: In the light of possible dangers, research becomes a moral duty. EMBO Reports, 8(10), 892–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teece, D., & Leih, S. (2016). Uncertainty, innovation, and dynamic capabilities: An introduction. California Management Review, 58(4), 5–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teece, D., Peteraf, M., & Leih, S. (2016). Dynamic capabilities and organizational agility: Risk, uncertainty, and strategy in the innovation economy. California Management Review, 58(4), 13–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teece, D. J., Pisano, G., & Shuen, A. (1997). Dynamic capabilities and strategic management. Strategic Management Journal, 18(7), 509–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Townsend, D. M., & Busenitz, L. W. (2015). Turning water into wine? Exploring the role of dynamic capabilities in early-stage capitalization processes. Journal of Business Venturing, 30(2), 292–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Townsend, D. M., Hunt, R. A., Beal, D. J., & Hyeong **, J. (2020). Venturing into the unknown: A meta-analytic assessment of uncertainty in entrepreneurship research. Academy of Management Proceedings, 2020(1), 17318.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. (1949). Human action: A treatise on economics [Ludwig von Mises Institute, www.mises.org/humanaction.asp].

  • Walker, G., & Weber, D. (1987). Supplier competition, uncertainty, and make-or-buy decisions. Academy of Management Journal, 30(3), 589–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, W. E., Harremoës, P., Rotmans, J., Van Der Sluijs, J. P., Van Asselt, M. B., Janssen, P., & Krayer von Krauss, M. P. (2003). Defining uncertainty: A conceptual basis for uncertainty management in model-based decision support. Integrated Assessment, 4(1), 5–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, W. E., Lempert, R, J., & Kwakkel, J. H. (2013). Deep uncertainty, entry. In S. Gass & M. C. Fu (Eds.), Encyclopedia of operations research and management science (pp. 395–402). (3rd ed.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, R. H., Jr. (1990). Adhocracy: The power to change. Whittle Direct Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weick, K. E. (1995). Sensemaking in organizations. Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. (1992, December). Quoted in Scientific American, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1985). The economic institutions of capitalism. Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, M., & Phan, P. (2017). AMP articles in an uncertain new world. Academy of Management Perspectives, 31, 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yager, R. R. (1999). A game-theoretic approach to decision making under uncertainty. Intelligent Systems in Accounting, Finance & Management, 8(2), 131–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zack, M. (1999). Develo** a knowledge strategy. California Management Review, 41(3), 125–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard J. Arend .

Appendices

Supplement on Knightian Uncertainty Issues

Knight’s (1921) seminal work on uncertainty has reverberated for over a century, especially in the entrepreneurship field. However, one hundred years of thinking about its ideas (and testing some of them) has exposed some issues worth considering now.

Knight’s (1921) work has had a large impact on entrepreneurship research. Even a century later, his conceptualization of uncertainty continues to influence work on the role of the entrepreneur in bearing specific informational challenges (e.g., Townsend et al., 2020). His delineation of risk from non-risk uncertainty—where the former entails problems that include the distributional information necessary to compute expected outcomes while the latter does not—has resulted in the latter being termed Knightian uncertainty. In his model, only under this kind of uncertainty can entrepreneurial profits arise—realized by bearing such uninsurable decisions through commitments and actions in pursuit of the profits that come to the residual holders of the contracts that constitute their ventures.

Knight’s Model as a Theory of Rents

Special for its time, Knight’s (1921) model can now be considered as just another explanation of super-normal rents. Knight’s super-normal profits are the result of revenues that are inflated by an undersupplied product combined with input costs that are reduced by their under-demand—with such inflation and reduction arising because of the low number of entrepreneurs-as-producers in that specific (new) product market. (Given that they constitute the few special people who are willing to bear uncertainty, they have little competition in selling their goods on one hand and buying their inputs on the other.) What differentiates Knight’s model is the story about what gives an entrepreneur the ability to produce the valued-but-undersupplied products—her unique judgment of what to do (i.e., which product to make, how, and in what quantity) when faced with non-risk uncertainty. (Luck, confidence, and the ability to execute also help.) In Knight’s model, the entrepreneur is the residual holder of a set of contracts because she alone is willing to bear the non-risk uncertainty as the leader of her venture that her employees have contracted with.Footnote 8 (Such a private arrangement also limits any spillover of her unique decisions based on her valuable judgment.) That story of rent-earning is no longer unique—as it simply presents just another version of the narrative where someone with a valuable, rare, inimitable, and appropriable capability can use it to gain an advantage (e.g., see the capability, resource, and knowledge-based views—e.g., Barney, 2002; Grant, 1996).

Although that kind of rent-logic is no longer special, the connections Knight’s (1921) version has with entrepreneurship, with strategic decision-making, and with uncertainty have been of continued interest, spiking again recently. Its connection with the entrepreneurship field remains strong because that field continues to look for defining theories, especially those that provide solid micro-economic arguments and that have survived decades; so it is not surprising it continues to be an easy and popular citation in addition to remaining an inspiration for new theorizing (e.g., Rindova & Courtney, 2020). Its connection with strategic decision-making remains strong, as managers struggle to deal with VUCA contexts where unknown unknowns and unimaginables make traditional tools based on scenarios, adaptability and options less applicable (Arend, 2020). And, its connection with uncertainty also remains strong, especially recently, as a renewed interest in incomplete informational problems involving unknowns has occurred. That renewed interest is a result of the historic wave of papers that had unfortunately replaced real uncertainty with risk (e.g., through subjective expected utility, beliefs and learning—Hodgson, 2011) ‘hitting a (predictable theory-related) wall’ when strategic decision-makers increasingly found themselves confronting uncertainty-related problems without any solid basis for the justified priors required for such expected-returns-based optimizations. And, so, the subsequent gold-rush to describe possible solutions to these unoptimizable problems was on. But, danger now looms when such follow-on work builds upon Knight’s model, especially when that model is loosely interpreted. These underappreciated dangers to academics and to practitioners are what we focus on here.

The Three Dangers of the Knightian Model

Knight’s (1921) model of entrepreneurial activity (one based on the market failure of incomplete information) involves three main dangers—one involving the main premise of the model, one involving the main implication of the model, and one involving the main definition of the model. We explain why those dangers can matter materially to academia and to practice after describing each.

The Premise Danger

For Knight’s (1921) story to work, there must exist, for all relevant parties, a minimum level of uncertainty that is beyond risky (i.e., without an expected value calculation, and so uninsurable). Essentially, if even one party confronts only risk in their decision, then that party could (profitably) provide insurance to others. And, when that occurs, no interesting party faces non-risk uncertainty and there is no entrepreneurial activity—as Knight would define it—required. No special judgment is needed. It is business-as-usual, as the downside is insured.

To illustrate, consider a one-factor production decision. It is a simple optimization problem with one input. The objective for the decision-maker is to maximize the profit on her productive effort. The benefit is accounted for in terms of revenue constituted from the output of the effort (e) multiplied by the output’s price (p). The variable cost is accounted for in terms of the square of the effort level exerted. And, there is a fixed investment (F) to enter that market, such that the problem is:

$$MAX \pi \left(e\right)=p\bullet e-{e}^{2}-F, p\ge 0, F>0$$

The optimal effort is a function of the price level (e* = p/2). There is a participation condition (assuming the opportunity cost is normalized to zero) of: \(p>2\sqrt{F}\). So, when the non-risk uncertainty concerns the value of p, then there is no optimization possible. It would then be unlikely that the decision-maker enters this market (i.e., when the value of p is unknowable, as well as its distribution, and the distribution of that distribution, and so on) because there is no guarantee or justified expectation of any positive gain from entering (e.g., given that the price may well lie below the participation condition). If, however, one of the relevant parties has confidence (i.e., subjectively perceives, regardless of any objective facts) that the expected price level lies above the participation condition, not only would she rationally enter the market, but she would also offer others the minimum participation price (plus an epsilon-sized bonus just above zero) to buy their product. Doing so essentially offers them insurance while also profiting from the expected difference in price without signaling what that level is (so it could not be calculated by others). In that case, she essentially ensures that no Knightian entrepreneurial activity occurs. (Note that we are not stating that she is using judgment while she correctly perceives the same level of uncertainty everyone else does, in which case she may be the sole Knightian entrepreneur here; what we are instead saying that she perceives a lower level of uncertainty than others and so does not need to apply any unusual judgment.)

Thus, this premise of a universality of a minimum uncertainty level (i.e., where that uncertainty is a level beyond risky) is dangerous because of its sensitivity to even a minor violation. It severely weakens the robustness of one the most famous theories explaining why entrepreneurs exist. From a theoretical perspective, while it is not unusual to assume that most factors are homogeneous across relevant parties (e.g., in order to simplify a model and focus its analysis), here there is more at stake because of the discontinuity that occurs when even one party differs. It is also troubling that the minimum necessary uncertainty level is singled out for homogeneity when so many factors related to it—like the judgment, confidence, and execution for those facing it—are all assumed heterogeneous. It is troubling because judgment—and the confidence in it needed to act—should be linked to the level of uncertainty being perceived. Reducing perceived uncertainty should increase the confidence a decision-maker has in her judgments, especially any that are unique. That link is embodied in experience. Heterogeneity in decision-maker judgment and confidence is based on past experience (Likierman, 2020), specifically here, on experiences with whatever level of uncertainty had been perceived. So, if experience not only links past perception to the current perception of uncertainty but also the current perception of uncertainty to judgment and its confidence, then the idea that differences in judgment can occur without related differences in perception seems unlikely. With that unlikeliness comes the violation of the focal premise of the model. With that unlikeliness also comes the question of whether the model can be tested (i.e., whether it is possible to separate differences in judgment about uncertainty from differences in perception of that uncertainty). And, with that question of premise and testing, comes the suspicion that such a model’s prescriptions may be quite weak in the real world.

Further, when the premise is wrong, we get a mislabeling of what Knightian entrepreneurship is. That mislabeling then poses legitimacy dangers for the original model and any model that builds upon it. For academia, holding the original model’s premise here means an under-appreciation in our theories of the sensitivity to uncertainty-level perception involved. It may also mean too few studies of decision-making and opportunity-exploiting based on that uncertainty-perception variance that Knight did not appear to consider.

Any practitioner misinterpreting Knight’s premise also faces dangers. There would be an under-appreciation of the variance in how people perceive the same event (e.g., Sjöberg, 2000), including in how they delineate risk from beyond risk, and that could lead to mistakes in how the practitioner predicts how rivals, customers and others will react to uncertainty-related problems. When the practitioner perceives non-risk uncertainty while others perceive only risk, she will miss out on using those others to insure what she believes is uninsurable (when she follows Knight). On the other hand, when she perceives only risk while others perceive non-risk uncertainty, she is likely to be exploited as an insurer for those others (when she follows Knight). In either case, following Knight’s premise may be very costly.

The Implication Danger

Knight’s (1921) story links non-risk uncertainty directly to entrepreneurial activity, doing so with the primary logical implication that if some non-risk uncertainty is necessary to induce entrepreneurial activity, then more of it will induce greater activity. The more of it refers to both quantity (i.e., more decisions or markets involving non-risk uncertainty) and quality (i.e., higher levels of that uncertainty). Similarly, the greater activity refers to both greater quantity (i.e., more entrepreneurs because more markets have the necessary uncertainty level or because any one market involves more uncertainties than one venture can exploit) and quality (i.e., better performance for the entrepreneur in markets that are providing wider or deeper uncertainty-related opportunities to exploit). This implication is based in the text of Knight’s (1921) book: he speaks to the larger profits that can be made when greater uncertainties exist in the markets that lack rivals with similar uncertainty-bearing capabilities (p. 230) as the: ‘…importance of uncertainty as a factor interfering with the perfect workings of competition…’. He also speaks to diminishing positive returns to entrepreneurship as being a function of uncertainty: (p. 286), as: ‘The question of diminishing returns from entrepreneurship is really a matter of the amount of uncertainty present’. (Note that diminishing returns can only occur when returns were positive and at levels high enough to measure material reductions.) And, prior to this, he commits to the linkage of uncertainty to income (p. 232) as: ‘this true uncertainty … accounts for the peculiar income of the entrepreneur’.

The danger arising from this implication is that we know uncertainty has costs, even for Knightian entrepreneurs. Knight (1921) even acknowledges—in a brief concession—that some of his entrepreneurs do fail because their judgment is wrong, their confidence is misplaced, or they are just unlucky. But, the most detailed and common Knightian story does not sufficiently reflect upon those failures, nor does it explicitly account for the other negative effects on the windfall-like incomes of the initially luckier entrepreneurs. It is inaccurate, theoretically, to concentrate a model on only the good side of a factor, especially when (even in 1921) the bad sides were known, or at least suspected. For example, it was and remains known that uncertainties have negative effects on even the performance of a Knightian entrepreneur (e.g., by suppressing demand from uncertainty-averse consumers). Not acknowledging that the kind of positive logical relationship that Knight implies between uncertainty and entrepreneurial outcomes is actually likely inaccurate (because it is incomplete) is dangerous. It is dangerous because holding to such relationships ensures that entrepreneurial activity—in terms of level and performance—will not be properly understood in terms of its complex association with uncertainty (e.g., in the field and in empirical studies). We may miss out on studying the interdependencies of the positive and negative effects of uncertainties, perhaps moderated by who the entrepreneur is, and which opportunities are involved. We may miss out on better specifying when entrepreneurial activity should actually arise and what policies there can be that decrease the linked negative effects of uncertainty. At the very least, any theoretical work that builds upon such a questionable implication stands on shaky ground and may damage the legitimacy of the fields it is contributing to.

The practical dangers arising from the overly-positive implication of Knight are even more stark. We know that real-world behaviors are adversely affected by uncertainty. For example, experiments have proven that risk-aversion and ambiguity-aversion are real and involve significant premia that reduce the efficiency of economic transactions and markets (e.g., Becker & Brownson, 1964). We have even seen the devastation that the multi-dimensionality of uncertainty linked to the recent Covid pandemic has had on the newer, smaller—often considered more entrepreneurial—ventures compared to more diversified, or more traditional corporations (e.g., Cui et al., 2023). In this light, the practical implication of Knight’s linkage of uncertainty with entrepreneurial activity and performance seems naïve (if not myopic) at best, and unfortunately dangerous at worst.Footnote 9 Interpreting Knight as truth about how uncertainty is linked to entrepreneurship will reduce the likelihood of better uncertainty-related opportunity outcomes in the field, and any policy based on those relationships will not work as expected (likely under-performing because it does not account for important negative effects).

The Definition Danger

Knight’s (1921) story is famous for its delineation of risk from uncertainty; however, its actual definition of that non-risk uncertainty is problematic due to its lack of crispness (e.g., Spender, 2006). The under-definition leads to multiple dangers: First, there are dangers that arise because there are actually many types of non-risk uncertainty that meet Knight’s definition (i.e., of being uninsurable, unpredictable, and unoptimizable).Footnote 10 But, only some of these types matter; and so, if these are confused with ones that do not matter, then damage is likely. For example, even under non-risk uncertainty some problems may only be trivially non-optimizable (e.g., when the unknown’s distribution is bounded by a narrow, but still profitable, range) while others can pose an existential threat (e.g., because the range of payoffs may include bankruptcy-level losses). Second, there are dangers that arise because the nature of the unknowableness of the focal uncertain factor lacks critical clarity. For example, when the unknowable is confused with the unknown-but-knowable, it can jeopardize venture performance (i.e., in terms of missing out on uncertainty reduction or spending too much on trying to reduce the irreducible).

The lack of clarity arises in Knight’s (1921) work because he mixes theoretical and practical concerns regarding how unknowableness can be dealt with. In theory, non-risk uncertainty is meant to be borne as is by entrepreneurs who have (or believe they have) better judgment when facing what they perceive is unknowable. That unknowableness must be irreducible prior to when the strategic decision must be made (Ramoglou, 2021) in Knight’s model. And, when the decision is right as that uncertainty is borne, the entrepreneur enjoys super-normal rents. However, and unfortunately, Knight also describes five other ways to deal with non-risk uncertainty where each of those ways transforms the ex ante unknown it into something (more) insurable or optimizable. These are practical approaches where the uncertainty is not borne, but rather is addressed through standard operating procedures where the expected outcome is in the form of normal rents.

The dangers to the field arising from the under-definition of Knight’s uncertainty are twofold: First, without a proper typology of the possible non-risk uncertainties, the term Knightian uncertainty involves too coarse a basis from which to build new theory. Without the provision of the full problem context—including the specific variant of non-risk uncertainty—any potential approaches to non-optimizable problems cannot be properly analyzed, let alone prescribed, with any legitimacy. For example, approaches for handling choice-option uncertainty differs from handling outcome-set uncertainty (e.g., Packard et al., 2017). Such differences in unknowns related to choices, outputs, probabilities and payoffs matter. For example, one unknown but bounded probability can often be dealt with in a decision; but, one unknown outcome or one (relatively unbounded) payoff that could occur for any choice theoretically cannot be dealt with. Second, without a clear delineation of the character of the unknowableness involved—specifically whether it is unknown-but-knowable or not—the confusion over what Knightian entrepreneurs actually are (i.e., those who bear the unknowable unknowns) will continue. They will be mistaken for entrepreneurs that, as part of their standard operating procedures, are only better at reducing a given unknown to something more known. That leads to mis-categorization, and the subsequent mistaken theorizing and testing that comes from it (e.g., to the point of making mistakes in prescriptions, investments, and empirical investigations).

The practical dangers arising from the under-definition are also twofold: The primary practical danger results from a lack of a proper typology of non-risk uncertainties. Without that typology, it is not possible for practitioners to study (in the field) which heuristics are effective against each type, nor is it possible to provide type-specific prescriptions from data, experience or theory to apply in the field. The second danger is that not having a clear delineation of unknowability is likely to result in mistakes involving treating unknowables as knowables and vice versa. In the real world, the former is likely to involve decision-makers trying to seek more information (e.g., through experimentation with the market), while the latter is likely to involve avoidance of the problem, or waiting it out, or retaining flexibility to respond to the outcome; with the respective dangers being in the forms of wasted effort and overconfidence, and of a wasted opportunity to gather the information to make a better proactive decision.

Discussion

Misinterpreting Knight’s (1921) model poses dangers: It should not be interpreted as a robust theory of entrepreneurship or of strategic decision-making under uncertainty, but instead as a model based on a knife’s edge premise over the shared minimum level of non-risk uncertainty perceived. It should not be interpreted as describing a simple positive relationship between non-risk uncertainty and entrepreneurial activity (or performance) because, in both the academic and practical worlds, uncertainty’s effects are complex and most often negative (Taleb, 2012). And, it should not be interpreted as clearly delineating all non-risk uncertainties in a useful manner, given there are many types of those uncertainties that should be addressed differently. All together, such potential dangers weaken Knight’s contribution to today’s understanding of entrepreneurial and strategically uncertain phenomena; but, that is not properly recognized by many who continue to cite it and build upon it. Such misinterpretations endanger both precise modeling and in-the-field testing, in addition to the subsequent practical prescriptions that could arise from each.

Reconsidering the premise danger, we know that a universally perceived minimum level of non-risk uncertainty for any focal problem is unlikely in the real world. We know from research that risk perception varies among business people (e.g., Mitchell, 1995). Similarly, we also know that uncertainty perception varies significantly across real decision-makers, including entrepreneurs, with differences in perceived uncertainty levels correlated with many factors, including those associated with the individual, the organization, and the community (e.g., Chawla et al., 2012; Downey & Slocum, 1975; Elenkov, 1997). Such findings are likely to extend to the perception of any critical level of non-risk uncertainty, ruining the necessary condition for Knightian entrepreneurship to exist. However, such heterogeneity in uncertainty perception could be exploited by policy-makers by making it easier for the relevant insurance-type markets to exist, so that those seeing less uncertainty can reduce it for those who see more, to the advantage of all. By adhering to Knight, however, that won’t be done. Nor will studying what it means to bear perceived uncertainty (e.g., psychologically) so that those who do so can be better understood and compensated (Dimov, 2018).

Reconsidering the implication dangers, we know that increases in the quality and quantity of real non-risk uncertainty are likely to work against real venture performance regardless of the potential for new opportunities it creates. For example, a high level of perceived non-risk uncertainty will delay if not decrease demand. Such effects strain the cash flows of most ventures. Further, widespread non-risk uncertainty caused by such events as the pandemic do more than cause decision-making hesitation and cash-flow anxiety to small business entrepreneurs; they can lead to strategic mistakes (Knight, 1921), ones that are existential in such contexts, and understood as such by entrepreneurs. Based on the psychological and behavioral economics research (e.g., Ellsberg, 1961; Kahneman & Tversky, 1979), common forms of uncertainty aversion will cause real entrepreneurs will pull back from investments, reducing even the future performance of their ventures. Added to those reactions, there are often regulatory restrictions on operations, hours, and on capacity, that all harm rather than help especially the new and small ventures. The negative consequences of increased uncertainty—that Knight fails to properly account for—squarely implies there exists an important role for government in reducing the perception, if not the real effects, of widespread uncertainties faced by the (entrepreneurial) small business sector. Real policy should not rely on Knight (1921).

Reconsidering the definitional dangers, we know that it is unlikely that real decision-makers delineate among the various types of non-risk uncertainty, let alone whether they treat each type differently. Questions over who should be responsible for perceiving the uncertainty level or type, how the choice is made whether it needs to be dealt with, and what the sequence is of how to do so, all need to be explored. In the real world, Knight’s model has little to say in answering those questions. In following it, we miss out on important avenues for research, for practice and for policy-making.

The implication is that policy-makers have a mandate—especially post-Covid—to fund such research, first in lab studies (where the types and amounts of uncertainties can be better controlled to see if those make a difference to perceptions and behaviors) and second, in the field (to see how those differences translate into reality).Footnote 11 That research should provide a better basis for hel** economic actors to perceive uncertainty, and then to build better toolkits and expertise for applying those tools when Knight’s non-risk uncertainties confront them. Rather than relying on simple interpretations of Knight (and his version of uncertainty), we as scholars of entrepreneurship and strategic management and decision-making need to confront the limitations and dangers of that model and move forward, and we hope that this supplement has provided a basis for so doing.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Arend, R.J. (2024). A New Typology of Uncertainty (for Decision-Making). In: Uncertainty in Strategic Decision Making. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-48553-4_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation