Emotion Concepts for Virtue Theory: From Aesthetic to Epistemic and Moral

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Traditional Indian Virtue Ethics for Today

Part of the book series: Palgrave Studies in Comparative East-West Philosophy ((PSCEWP))

Abstract

In “Emotion Concepts for Virtue Theory: From Epistemic and Moral to Aesthetic,” Lisa Widdison addresses a meta-philosophical issue in virtue theory, the historically problematic role of emotions in moral judgement, and in motivating virtue. Contemporary virtue epistemologists look to character traits that are relevant to inquiry, such as intellectual courage, carefulness and open-mindedness as marks of intellectual virtue. Both virtue ethicists and virtue epistemologists may also construe emotions as embodied judgements which express moral and epistemic value. However, the cognitive language of emotions as ‘self-interested judgments of value’ leaves a gap aesthetic judgment may fill. In contrast with egotistical or deterministic emotions, a path to empathy, harmony and compassion is affectively regulated by judgments of taste. By following Bharatamuni (Nāṭyaśāstra, 200 CE) and Abhinavagupta (950 CE) through a paradigmatic model of fully graded aesthetic emotion-type distinctions, the discourse around bhavas and rasas (ordinary and universalized emotion, respectively) provides a basis to link the aesthetic stance to free will, agentive responsibility and an infusion of pathos required to motivate a character trait of harmony. Lisa maintains that in processing aesthetic judgments, emotions become reflective, or operate without a settled objective, and so can harmonize actions with moral interests. It is possible to make a fine-tuned analysis of cognitive, occurrent states of personal emotion, and open-ended, universalized emotions, which constitute aesthetic experiences. The finely graded distinctions of affect in Śaiva non-dualism reveal an emotional agency which presupposes the unity of cognition with affect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 96.29
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Vidyākara, and Daniel Henry Holmes. Ingalls, trans., Kosambi and Gokhale, eds. (1957). Subhāṣitaratnakoṣa: Sanskrit Poetry, from Vidyākara’s Treasurȳ. Cambridge Harvard Oriental Series.

    In the original Sanskrit page 226: khlānāṃ kharjūrakṣitaruhakaṭhoraṃ kva ca manaḥ / kva conmīlanmallīkusumasukumārāḥ kavigiraḥ / itīmaṃ vyāmohaṃ parihara vicitrāḥ śṛṇu kathā / yathāyaṃ pīyūṣadyutirupalakhaṇḍaṃ dravayati //. Translated in Sanskrit Poetry from Vidyākara’s Treasury, by Daniel H. Ingalls (1965) 1278/page 253.

  2. 2.

    Quoted from the Gītā II:70.

  3. 3.

    See Lawrence McCrea on the theistic teleological progression of poetic theory into the established aesthetic theory of aesthetic emotion in 11th CE Kashmir. McCrea (2009)

  4. 4.

    ibid., (2004, 70).

  5. 5.

    Boris Marjanovic trans. Abhinavagupta, Gitartha Samgraha, (2004, 78).

  6. 6.

    Pluhar trans. 2010, 87,238§.

  7. 7.

    Boruah remarks, the paradox of emotion in fiction disappears by taking existential and evaluative beliefs as separate (1988, 125).

  8. 8.

    (NS 7.7) tatrāṣṭau bāvāḥ sthāyinaḥ / trayastriṃśadvyabhicāriṇaḥ / aṣṭau sātvikā iti bhedāḥ / evamete kāvyarasabhivyaktihetava ekonapañcāśadbhāvāḥ pratyavagantavyāḥ / ebhyaśca sāmānyaguṇayogena rasā niṣpadyante //.

  9. 9.

    bhavati cātra ślokaḥyo’artho hṛdayasaṃvādi tasya bhāvo rasodbhavaḥ / śarīraṃ vyāpyate tena śuṣkaṃ kāṣṭhabhivāgninā (NS 7.7).

  10. 10.

    Aristotle, Poetics, IX.

  11. 11.

    Gnoli, (1956, 60).

  12. 12.

    Abh. VI, See Gnoli (1956, 26).

  13. 13.

    CJ §59, 229.

  14. 14.

    Plato (1997), in the Ion reveals the poets to be more of a conduit of divine transmission than divinely inspired visionaries, in part because Ion has no idea what it is his poetry actually means himself.

  15. 15.

    Beginning with a cognitive theory of emotions defended by the Stoic philosopher, Seneca, affective response or feeling in aesthetic experience is not necessarily considered to be an emotion, mainly because it is not construed as an evaluative judgment to which the agent assents. In a stoic cognitivism of ‘emotions,’ ‘first movements,’ or embodied affective responses, abide on a non-cognitive lower level. “Real” emotions are taken as higher order cognitive evaluations reaching assent to judgment. This is not the case for Posidonius, for whom the irrational nature of affect is attuned in aesthetic experience precisely because both poetics and affect function through harmonization of a distinct part of the soul. On Seneca’s picture, what one names aestheticized-emotions are merely a first-order responses, which abide below the threshold of cognitive evaluation, and are thereby insufficient to constitute the paradigmatic minimally two-tiered structure of real ‘emotions.’ Seneca’s own argument rests on the non-propositional nature of wordless music, and the lack of a determinate object on which to base a judgment of it. See Richard Sorabji, Emotion and Peace of Mind.

  16. 16.

    The process of imaginative role-play is a (āvaraṇa-bhaṅga) breaking of obscurity, see Chakrabarti (2009, 197).

  17. 17.

    The Stoics linked emotion’s place in moral dispositions to naturally follow from emotion’s role in epistemic dispositions. Stoics naturally advocate disciplining emotional dispositions for an agent’s benefit. Sorabji, 7.

  18. 18.

    Nussbaum (1993) follows Galen on this: “Posidonius ‘completely departed’ (telos apechorisen), both from Chrysippus’ view that they are identical with judgments and from Zeno’s view that they supervene on and are necessarily produced by judgments: Nor he does not regard the passions either as judgments or as supervening upon judgments, but as coming about through the thumoeidetic and epithumetic power” (Passions and Perceptions, 110).

  19. 19.

    Seneca, De Ira, Book II.

  20. 20.

    It is worth differentiating the view of Posidonius from Chrysiuppus and Zeno on this point, the latter of whom Seneca follows. For Chrysiuppus, all emotions are faulty judgments and should be eradicated. If emotions are construed as irrational then they make us epistemically vulnerable. For the sake of explaining why the Stoics take up poetry as a practice, given the call for attacking it beginning with the rationalist, Plato, Martha Nussbaum has the positions mapped out: “The paradox of Stoic poetry,” according to Nussbaum, is about the consensus of Hellenistic philosophers: “that poetry makes its impact on the soul above all by altering its passions” but ironically, many influential Stoics were themselves marvels of poetic erudition. (Passions and Perceptions, 98).

  21. 21.

    Seneca 2010. “The Pumpkinification of Claudius the God” (Apocolocyntosis). See: Seneca: Anger, Mercy, Revenge. Martha Nussbaum, trans.

  22. 22.

    Ibid., p. 202.

  23. 23.

    Seneca, in particular prescribes a program of discipline in his counsel to extirpate all practices leading to anger.

  24. 24.

    Ibid., 219, pp. 63.

  25. 25.

    CJ 187 Pluhar, 26 [This cryptic phrasing might be one reason to suppose that aesthetic pleasure precedes the process of judging, but logically, as we shall see this thought should be avoided.]

  26. 26.

    209 Kant, CJ 268, Pluhar, pp. 127210 Kant, OBS 47–8.

  27. 27.

    Zagzebski, Linda. Virtues of the Mind. 2002, 243.

  28. 28.

    Kant’s theory of reflective judging is integral to this account, but up to this point we could just as well consider David Hume’s of the Standard of Taste. The key feature of Kant’s theory here, is that the judgment of taste must be theoretically communicable. The aesthetic experience is one in which we can imagine others would likely feel the same way in similar circumstances, even if embodied responses, such as trembling or crying differ between members of the audience. The judgment of taste is communicable in a way that is unlike lower-order affective responses.

  29. 29.

    CJ Pluhar, 186/318.

  30. 30.

    Sen Aesthetic Enjoyment, XXI.

  31. 31.

    Pluhar, 2010, 91 §241.

  32. 32.

    Abhinavagupta (2014), Jaideva Singh trans, 2014, 39.

  33. 33.

    Wittgenstein & Kolak 1998, 48.

  34. 34.

    Chatterjee. Trans. Śrī Tantrāloka 2008, 55–56.

  35. 35.

    Ibid., 49.

  36. 36.

    Kant, Pluhar trans. 2010, 91.

  37. 37.

    Kṣemdra (1964), Aucityavicārcarcā 118, Aucitya is literally a concept of propriety, fitness, and appropriateness, but could be translated as aptness.

References

  • Abhinavagupta. 2014. Singh, J., Joo, L., & Bäumer, B. Parā-Trīśikā-vivaraṇa: The secret of tantric mysticism. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abhinavagupta. 2004. Marjanovic, Boris. Trans. Gītārthasaṁgraha. Varanasi: Indica Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abhinavagupta. 2008. Chatterjee, Gautam. Trans. Śrī Tantrālokaḥ. Indian Mind, Varanasi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abhinavagupta and Bharatamuni. 1992. The Nāṭyaśāstra of Bharata, with the Abhinavabhāratī of Abhinavagupta, Vol. 1, 4th ed. Ed. K. Krishnamoorthy. Baroda: Oriental Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Vol. 2. Jonathan Barnes, trans. Princeton University Press: 2316–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharyya, K. C. 2011. “The Concept of Rasa (1930).” Indian Philosophy in English from Renaissance to Independence. edited by Nalini Bhushan and Jay L. Garfield. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boruah, Bijoy. 2016. Arindam Chakrabarti, ed. “The impersonal Subjectivity of Aesthetic Emotion” in Bloomsbury research handbook of Indian aesthetics and the philosophy of art. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakrabarti, Arindam. 2009. “Play, Pleasure, Pain: Ownerless Emotions in Rasa- Aesthetics.” In History of Science, Philosophy, and Culture in Indian Civilization. Vol. XV Part III. ed. D.P. Chattopadhyaya and Amiya Dev (New Delhi: Center for Study in Civilizations). pp. 189–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakrabarti, Arindam. 2005.“Heart of Repose, The Repose of the Heart: A Phenomenological Analysis of the Concept of Viśrānti” in Samarasya: Studies in Indian Arts, Philosophy, and Interreligious Dialogue: in Honour of Bettina Bäumer. Edited by Sadananda Das and Ernst Fürlinger. New Delhi: D.K. Printworld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarti, Sitansu Sekhar. 2019. “Tagore-Wittgenstein Interface: The poet’s activism and virtue ethics.” Tagore, Einstein and the Nature of Reality: Literary and Philosophical Reflections. Partha Ghose (ed.) London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dās, Bhagavan. 1953. The science of emotions. Madras, India: Theosophical Pub. House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gnoli, Raniero. 1956. The aesthetic experience according to Abhinavagupta. Roma: Is. M.E.O.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, Paul. “Alva Noë, Strange Tools: Art and Human Nature” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XCIV No. 1, January 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanfling, Oswald. “Five Kinds of Distance” British Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 40, No. 1, January 2000 p 89–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2010. Werner S. Pluhar. trans. Critique of Judgment. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keltner, Dacher. 2023 Awe: The Transformative Power of Everyday Wonder. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kṣemendra. 1964. Ācārya Śri Brajmohan Jhā. Ed. Aucityavicārcarcā. Vidyabhawan Sanskrit Granthamala, Chowkhamba.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, Jean François. 1991. Lessons on the Analytic of the sublime Kant’s Critique of judgment, sections §23–29. Translated by Elizaberh Ronenberg. Meridian.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrea, L. J. (2009). The teleology of poetics in medieval Kashmir. Published by the Dept. of Sanskrit and Indian Studies, Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva “Strange Tools: Art and Human Nature: A Precis” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. XCIV No. 1, January 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2008. Upheavals of thought: the intelligence of emotions. Indianapolis, Hackett

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1993. “Poetry and the Passions: two Stoic views” in Passions and Perceptions: studies in Hellenistic philosophy of mind. Edited by Jacques Brunschwig, and Martha C. Nussbaum. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1997 John M. Cooper Ed., Paul Woodruff trans. “Ion” in Complete Works. Cambridge; Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seneca, Lucius Annaeus. 2010. Nussbaum, Martha. Trans. “The Pumpkinification of Claudius the God”. and “On Anger” trans. Kaster. In Anger, Mercy, Revenge. Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaper, Eva. Pleasure, preference and value: studies in philosophical aesthetics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr., 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, Richard. 2000. Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation To Christian Temptation The Gifford Lectures. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Vidyākara, and Daniel Henry Holmes. Ingalls, trans., Kosambi and Gokhale, eds. (1957). Subhāṣitaratnakoṣa: Sanskrit Poetry, from Vidyākara’s Treasury. Cambridge Harvard Oriental Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. Spring 2001 “Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline” The Three penny Review.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L., & Kolak, D. (1998). Wittgenstein’s tractatus. Mayfield Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 2002. Virtues of the mind: an inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 2001. “Rediscovering Understanding” in Knowledge, Truth and Duty, edited by Matthias Steup. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lisa Widdison .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Widdison, L. (2024). Emotion Concepts for Virtue Theory: From Aesthetic to Epistemic and Moral. In: Chakravarti, S.S., Chatterjee, A., Chakravarti, A., Widdison, L. (eds) Traditional Indian Virtue Ethics for Today. Palgrave Studies in Comparative East-West Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-47972-4_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation