Part of the book series: Research in Mathematics Education ((RME))

  • 235 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, we describe reflected abstraction and discuss its implications for empirical research into the teaching and learning of mathematics. We discuss the relationship between reflected abstraction and other theoretical constructs within Piaget’s genetic epistemology, and the mathematics education research literature generally. With this background established, we outline various implications of reflected abstraction for students’ learning of mathematics and teachers’ construction of pedagogical content knowledge. We then consider strategies for promoting reflected abstractions and propose explicit standards of evidence for supporting valid claims about whether an individual has constructed schemes at the level of reflected thought. We conclude by outlining pertinent questions that mathematics education researchers might pursue regarding either the necessary conditions for promoting reflected abstractions or the implications of reflected schemes for students’ mathematical activity and teachers’ instructional practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Because Piaget neither considered cognitive development a process determined by environmental pressures nor biological maturation, his theory is often referred to as a middle-ground position, third possibility, or tertium quid (Gallagher & Reid, 2002, p. 23).

  2. 2.

    We note that pseudo-empirical, reflecting, reflected, and metareflection are non-mutually exclusive forms of abstraction.

  3. 3.

    Ellis, Lockwood, and Paoletti (this volume) provide thorough descriptions of empirical, pseudo-empirical, and reflecting abstraction.

  4. 4.

    A reflected abstraction is a scheme constructed at the level of reflected thought.

  5. 5.

    See the discussion of reflecting abstraction later in this chapter.

  6. 6.

    We use symbol to refer to any object that evokes in an individual an “abstracted representation” of experience and associated meanings (von Glasersfeld, 1995, p. 99). The object may be a stimulus in one’s sensory field (i.e., exogeneous) or a representation of experience (i.e., endogenous).

  7. 7.

    Consider, for example, the common abstraction that a product is always greater than its factors (i.e., “multiplication makes bigger”).

  8. 8.

    Piaget encapsulates differentiation within the projective aspect of reflecting abstraction. We make differentiation explicit because it is one of the key distinctions between reflecting abstraction and pseudo-empirical abstraction.

  9. 9.

    Throughout this chapter, we use “representation” in a manner consistent with von Glasersfeld’s (1995) interpretation of how Piaget applied the term: “For Piaget, representation is always the replay, or re-construction from memory, of a past experience and not a picture of something else, let alone a picture of the real world” (p. 59).

  10. 10.

    For this to be an appropriate method for comparing the “size” (i.e., non-quantitative comparison) of the angles, the student must recognize that the selected point on the terminal must be the same distance away from the vertex of each angle—a fact that the student had the opportunity to pseudo-empirically abstract while engaged in the activity displayed in Figure 8.4.

  11. 11.

    Regarding the décalage, or temporal delay, between reflecting and reflected abstraction, Piaget (2001) explained, “The subject becomes conscious of the result of his acts—which requires a simple static read-off—before becoming conscious of their mechanism and their exact unfolding—which requires the reconstruction of a process” (p. 191).

  12. 12.

    B and R, respectively, represent the length of the blue and red walls; b represents the length of a blue block and r represents the length of a red block.

  13. 13.

    Piaget and Duckworth’s (1968) book On the Development of Memory and Identity necessitates this qualification.

  14. 14.

    Throughout this chapter, we use “represent” (without the hyphen) to refer to the action of reifying a re-presentation of experience in the form of a symbol.

  15. 15.

    Piaget referred to symbols as “internalized imitations,” which are necessarily grounded in the knowing subject’s actions (Ginsburg & Opper, 1988, p. 74).

  16. 16.

    Tillema (this volume) provides a thorough description of scheme from a Piagetian perspective.

  17. 17.

    It is possible for figurative schemes to emerge via empirical and pseudo-empirical abstractions, but such schemes are, by definition, non-operative (see the discussion of figurative and operative knowledge structures below). Logico-mathematical knowledge, on the other hand, must be operative, meaning that the schemes it entails are composed of reversible mental actions that can be applied to a generic class of objects without regard for an initial state.

  18. 18.

    The terminal point of an angle in standard position is the intersection of the terminal ray and a circle centered at the angle’s vertex.

  19. 19.

    Thompson, Byerley, and O’Bryan (this volume) provide a thorough description of imagery from a Piagetian perspective.

  20. 20.

    Also, see the next section where we discuss figurative thought and operative thought.

  21. 21.

    Moore, Stevens, Tasova, and Liang (this volume) provide a detailed description of figurative and operative modes of thought.

  22. 22.

    A ratio is a multiplicative comparison of the measures of two constant (non-varying) quantities, while a rate defines a proportional relationship between varying quantities’ measures (Thompson & Thompson, 1992). Constructing a rate therefore involves images of smooth continuous variation (Thompson & Carlson, 2017), as well as the expectation that as two quantities covary, multiplicative comparisons of their measures remain invariant.

  23. 23.

    Dubinsky (1991) used the term “reflective abstractions,” and so we follow his lead in this section. Piaget used “reflective abstraction” generally to describe abstraction that is not empirical or pseudo-empirical. Its use does not distinguish between reflecting abstractions, the construction of reflected schemes, and meta-reflection. Dubinsky does not himself distinguish between these more nuanced characterizations of abstraction in his theory, although we would argue that his use of “reflective abstraction” might be better interpreted as “reflecting abstraction” consistent with how we’ve described the construct in this chapter.

  24. 24.

    The terms “schemes,” “schemas,” and “schemata” have appeared in English translations of Piaget’s work as plurals of “scheme.”

  25. 25.

    This example is related to quantitative reasoning and covariational reasoning (see the next section).

  26. 26.

    Boyce (this volume) provides a detailed description of quantitative reasoning.

  27. 27.

    See our example in the previous section.

  28. 28.

    Steffe and Thompson (2000) distinguished first- and second-order observers as follows: “first-order observers address what someone understands, while second-order observers address what they understand about what the other person could understand” (p. 303, italics in original).

  29. 29.

    Thompson (2002) defined an epistemic student not as “anyone in particular. Rather, we speak generically of a person, as in ‘Suppose a person understands fractions as ‘so many out of so many …” Images of this type allow us to propose ways of thinking that are not specific to any one person, yet they are not ‘disembodied cognizing’” (p. 195). These images are what we mean by epistemic ways of understanding. Develo** images of multiple ways of understanding students in a class could have is highly useful in hel** teachers react productively in the moment by hel** them recognize the potential way of understanding a student could have that is manifesting in particular behaviors.

References

  • Beth, E. W., & Piaget, J. (1966). Mathematical epistemology and psychology (W. Mays, Trans.). D. Riedel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, M., Jacobs, S., Coe, E., Larsen, S., & Hsu, E. T. (2002). Applying covariational reasoning while modeling dynamic events: A framework and a study. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 33(5), 352–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, M. (1988). Constructive evolution: Origins and development of Piaget’s thought. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobb, P. (2007). Putting philosophy to work: Co** with multiple theoretical perspectives. In F. K. Lester (Ed.), Second handbook of research on mathematics teaching and learning (Vol. 1, pp. 1–38). Information Age Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1902). The child and the curriculum. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorko, A. (2019). Professors’ intentions and student learning in an online homework assignment. In A. Weinberg, D. Moore-Russo, H. Soto, & M. Wawro (Eds.), Proceedings of the 22nd annual conference on research in undergraduate mathematics education (pp. 172–179).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubinsky, E. (1991). Reflective abstraction in advanced mathematical thinking. In D. Tall (Ed.), Advanced mathematical thinking (pp. 95–123). Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, J. M., & Reid, D. K. (2002). The learning theory of Piaget and Inhelder. iUniverse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, H., & Opper, S. (1988). Piaget 's theory of intellectual development. Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, H. E., & Vonèche, J. J. (1977). The essential Piaget: An interpretative reference and guide. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harel, G. (2007). The DNR system as a conceptual framework for curriculum development and instruction. In R. Lesh, J. J. Kaput, & E. Hamilton (Eds.), Foundations for the future in mathematics education. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harel, G. (2008a). DNR perspective on mathematics curriculum and instruction part I: Focus on proving. Zentralblatt für Didaktik der Mathematik, 40, 487–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harel, G. (2008b). A DNR perspective on mathematics curriculum and instruction, part II: With reference to teacher’s knowledge base. Zentralblatt für Didaktik der Mathematik, 40, 893–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harel, G., & Koichu, B. (2010). An operational definition of learning. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 29, 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardison, H. L., & Lee, H. Y. (2020). Funky protractors for exploring angle measure. Mathematics Teacher: Learning and Teaching PK-12, 113(3), 229–232. https://doi.org/10.5951/MTLT.2019.0214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackiw, N. (2011). The geometer’s sketchpad v5. 0. Key Curriculum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, H. L. (2015). Secondary students’ quantification of ratio and rate: A framework for reasoning about change in covarying quantities. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 17(1), 64–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kilpatrick, J. (1992). A history of research in mathematics education. In D. A. Grouws (Ed.), Handbook of research on mathematics teaching and learning (pp. 3–38). National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lew, K. M., Fukawa-Connelly, T., Mejía-Ramos, J. P., & Weber, K. (2016). Lectures in advanced mathematics: Why students might not understand what the professor is trying to convey. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 47(2), 162–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liang, B. (2020). Theorizing teachers’ mathematical learning in the context of student-teacher interaction: A lens of decentering. In S. S. Karunakaran, Z. Reed, & A. Higgins (Eds.), Proceedings of the 23rd annual conference on research in undergraduate mathematics education (pp. 742–751). Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J. (2003). How design experiments can inform a rethinking of transfer and vice versa. Educational Researcher, 32(1), 17–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J. (2006). Alternative perspectives on the transfer of learning: History, issues, and challenges for future research. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 15(4), 431–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J. (2008). When students don’t apply the knowledge you think they have, rethink your assumptions about transfer. In M. Carlson & C. Rasmussen (Eds.), Making the connection: Research and teaching in undergraduate mathematics (pp. 289–304). Mathematical Association of America.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J. (2012). The actor-oriented transfer perspective and its contributions to educational research and practice. Educational Psychologist, 47(3), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J., Rhodehamel, B., & Hohensee, C. (2012). “Noticing” as an alternative transfer of learning process. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 21(3), 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J., & Siebert, D. (2002). Quantitative reasoning in a reconceived view of transfer. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 21, 87–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobato, J., & Thanheiser, E. (2002). Develo** understanding of ratio as measure as a foundation for slope. Making sense of fractions, ratios, and proportions, 162–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. C. (2010). The role of quantitative reasoning in precalculus students' learning central concepts of trigonometry (unpublished doctoral dissertation). Arizona State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. C. (2014). Quantitative reasoning and the sine function: The case of Zac. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 45(1), 102–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. C., LaForest, K. R., & Kim, H. J. (2016). Putting the unit in pre-service secondary teachers' unit circle. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 92(2), 221–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. C., Paoletti, T., & Musgrave, S. (2014). Complexities in students’ construction of the polar coordinate system. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 36, 135–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. C., Stevens, I. E., Paoletti, T., Hobson, N. L., & Liang, B. (2019). Pre-service teachers’ figurative and operative graphing actions. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 56, 100692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, U. (2009). Infancy. In U. Müller, J. Carpendale, & L. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Piaget (Cambridge companions to philosophy) (pp. 200–228). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Six psychological studies. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970). Genetic epistemology. W. W. Norton & Company Inc.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and knowledge. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1977). Psychology and epistemology: Towards a theory of knowledge. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (2001). Studies in reflecting abstraction. Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., & Duckworth, E. (1968). On the development of memory and identity (Vol. 2). Clark University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L., & Thompson, P. W. (1998). Re-thinking covariation from a quantitative perspective: Simultaneous continuous variation. In Paper presented at the annual meeting of the psychology of mathematics education-North America. North Carolina State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J. L. (1988). Intensive quantity and referent transforming arithmetic operations. In J. Hiebert & M. Behr (Eds.), Number concepts and operations in the middle grades (Vol. 2, pp. 41–52). National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, L. S. (1970). Reconstruction of educational research. Review of Educational Research, 40(3), 371–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, L. S. (1974). The psychology of school subjects: A premature obituary? Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 11(4), 319–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, L. S. (1986). Those who understand: Knowledge growth in teaching. Educational Researcher, 15(2), 4–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, L. S. (1987). Knowledge and teaching: Foundations of the new reform. Harvard Educational Review, 57(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, J., & Thompson, P. W. (2008). Toward a framework for the development of mathematical knowledge for teaching. Journal of Mathematics Teacher Education, 11, 499–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, M. (1995). Reconstructing mathematics pedagogy from a constructivist perspective. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 26, 114–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, M. A., & Placa, N. (2012). Reasoning about intensive quantities in whole-number multiplication? A possible basis for ratio understanding. For the Learning of Mathematics, 32(2), 35–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. P., III, & Thompson, P. W. (2008). Quantitative reasoning and the development of algebraic reasoning. In J. J. Kaput, D. W. Carraher, & M. L. Blanton (Eds.), Algebra in the early grades (pp. 95–132). Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steffe, L. P., von Glasersfeld, E., Richards, J., & Cobb, P. (1983). Children’s counting types: Philosophy, theory, and application. Praeger Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steffe, L. P., & Thompson, P. W. (2000). Teaching experiment methodology: Underlying principles and essential elements. In A. E. Kelly & R. A. Lesh (Eds.), Handbook of research design in mathematics and science education (pp. 267–307). Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallman, M. (2015). An examination of the effect of a secondary teacher’s image of instructional constraints on his enacted subject matter knowledge. Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, School of Mathematical and Statistical Sciences, Arizona State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallman, M. A. (2021). Investigating the transformation of a secondary teacher’s knowledge of trigonometric functions. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 62, 100869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallman, M. A., & Frank, K. M. (2020). Angle measure, quantitative reasoning, and instructional coherence: An examination of the role of mathematical ways of thinking as a component of teachers’ knowledge base. Journal of Mathematics Teacher Education, 23(1), 69–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallman, M. A., & Uscanga, R. (2020). Managing students’ mathematics anxiety in the context of online learning environments. In J. P. Howard & J. F. Beyers (Eds.), Teaching and learning mathematics online (pp. 189–216). CRC Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tallman, M. A., & Weaver, J. (2018). Reflected abstraction as a mechanism for develo** pedagogical content knowledge. In T. E. Hodges, G. J. Roy, & A. M. Tyminski (Eds.), Proceedings of the 40th annual meetings of the north American chapter of the international group for the psychology of mathematics education (pp. 476–483). University of South Carolina & Clemson University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (1985). Experience, problem solving, and learning mathematics: Considerations in develo** mathematics curricula. In E. A. Silver (Ed.), Teaching and learning mathematical problem solving: Multiple research perspectives (pp. 189–243). Earlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (1988). Quantitative concepts as a foundation for algebra. In M. Behr (Ed.), Proceedings of the annual meeting of the North American chapter of the international group for the psychology of mathematics education (Vol. 1, pp. 163–170).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (1990). A theoretical model of quantity-based reasoning in arithmetic and algebra. Center for Research in Mathematics & Science Education/San Diego State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (1993). Quantitative reasoning, complexity, and additive structures. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 25(3), 165–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (1994). The development of the concept of speed and its relationship to concepts of rate. In G. Harel & J. Confrey (Eds.), The development of multiplicative reasoning in the learning of mathematics (pp. 181–234). SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (2002). Didactic objects and didactic models in radical constructivism. In K. Gravvemeijer, R. Lehrer, B. V. Oers, & L. Verschaffel (Eds.), Symbolizing, modeling, and tool use in mathematics education (pp. 191–212). Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (2008). Conceptual analysis of mathematical ideas: Some spadework at the foundation of mathematics education. Proceedings of the annual meeting of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, 1, 45–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (2011). Quantitative reasoning and mathematical modeling. In L. L. Hatfield, S. Chamberlain, & S. Belbase (Eds.), New perspectives and directions for collaborative research in mathematics education (pp. 33–57). University of Wyoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W. (2013). In the absence of meaning. In K. Leatham (Ed.), Vital directions for research in mathematics education (pp. 57–90). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W., & Carlson, M. P. (2017). Variation, covariation, and functions: Foundational ways of thinking mathematically. In J. Cai (Ed.), Compendium for research in mathematics education (pp. 421–456). National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W., Carlson, M. P., Byerley, C., & Hatfield, N. (2014). Schemes for thinking with magnitudes: An hypothesis about foundational reasoning abilities in algebra. In K. C. Moore, L. P. Steffe, & L. L. Hatfield (Eds.), Epistemic algebra students: Emerging models of students’ algebraic knowing. (WISDOMe Monographs) (pp. 1–24). University of Wyoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. W., & Thompson, A. G. (1992, April). Images of rate. In Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American educational research association.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glaserfeld, E. (1995). Radical constructivism: A way of knowing and learning. RoutledgeFalmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (2007). In M. Larochelle (Ed.), Key works in radical constructivism. Sense.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Humboldt, W. (1907). Werke (Vol. 7). Leitmann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Much of what we express in this chapter has its origins in conversations we have had with Patrick Thompson. Throughout this chapter, we acknowledge where our writing was informed by or connects with Pat Thompson’s published work. However, these references do not adequately represent his influence on our understanding of Piaget’s theory. We are indebted to Pat for his many years of hel** us navigate the complexities of Piaget’s genetic epistemology. This chapter would not have been possible without our benefiting from his expertise.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael A. Tallman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tallman, M.A., O’Bryan, A.E. (2024). Reflected Abstraction. In: Dawkins, P.C., Hackenberg, A.J., Norton, A. (eds) Piaget’s Genetic Epistemology for Mathematics Education Research. Research in Mathematics Education. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-47386-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-47386-9_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-47385-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-47386-9

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation