Basic Primer on Principles and Philosophy Applicable to Reproductive Bioethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Case Studies in the Ethics of Assisted Reproduction

Abstract

Various principles and frameworks are useful in guiding ethical shared decision making as well as policy development in reproductive medicine. These include: ethical theories (e.g., principilism, utilitarianism) and principles (e.g., moral status) as well as additional considerations (e.g., informed consent). No one of these ethical models or frameworks must be adopted or should be applied unilaterally. In some cases, the application of varied ethical models may yield to conflicting outcomes. Nevertheless, each of these theories gives rise to considerations which are important to consider to completely appreciate the complex ethical dimensions of moral dilemmas in reproductive ethics. This chapter will serve as a reference point for all chapters that follow to provide background and context for ethical theories used elsewhere in this casebook.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (Brazil)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Beauchamp at 38 (referencing Percival).

  2. 2.

    Beauchamp and Childress at 7.

  3. 3.

    These principles are set forth in Beauchamp and Childress (99–313).

  4. 4.

    These four principles originate from the Belmont Report, which sought to protect human research participants, and from foundational bioethics texts.

  5. 5.

    King, Autonomy.

  6. 6.

    See Jasanoff at 249, 256.

  7. 7.

    Beauchamp and Childress at 162–164.

  8. 8.

    See, e.g., Sandel, Goodwin.

  9. 9.

    Munson at 383.

  10. 10.

    Kant, The Good Will and the Categorical Imperative.

  11. 11.

    Ross, The Right and The Good, at 21–27.

  12. 12.

    Ross, The Right and The Good, 21–27.

  13. 13.

    See Jonsen.

  14. 14.

    See Gilligan.

  15. 15.

    See Gilligan.

  16. 16.

    See Norlock.

  17. 17.

    See Norlock, Scully.

  18. 18.

    Chambers at 40.

  19. 19.

    See The Oxford Handbook of Reproductive Ethics. Oxford University Press. January 2016.

  20. 20.

    See Sister Song.

  21. 21.

    See In Our Own Voice, Sister Song.

  22. 22.

    See O’Neill, Some Limits of Informed Consent. See also O’Neill, Autonomy, and Luna and Luker.

  23. 23.

    See Emmanuel.

  24. 24.

    Sandel at 42. Timmons at 51–52.

  25. 25.

    Timmons 51–52.

  26. 26.

    See Macklin.

References

  • Beauchamp, T.L., Standing on Principles : Collected Essays, Oxford University Press, Incorporated, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L. & Childress, J.F. (2013). Principles of biomedical ethics (7th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belmont Report: Ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. (1979). U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, available at https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/belmont-report/read-the-belmont-report/index.html

  • Chambers, T. (2001). The fiction of bioethics: A précis. American Journal of Bioethics, 1(1), 40–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emanuel E.J. & Thompson D. (2008), Concept of Conflicts of interest in Medical Research: Historical Developments in The Oxford Textbook of Clinical Research Ethics, 760 (Emanuel E. at el. ed. Oxford).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982), In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, M. (2020). Policing the Womb. In Policing the Womb: Invisible Women and the Criminalization of Motherhood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2016). The Ethics of Invention: Technology and the Human Future (1st Ed.) W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen AR. Casuistry as methodology in clinical ethics. Theor Med. 1991 Dec ;12(4):295–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2015). The Good Will and the Categorical Imperative, in Shaffer-Landau, R. The Ethical Life: Fundamental readings in ethics and moral problems (3rd ed.) (87–99). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, L. Autonomy, Regulation, and Clinical Duties: Balancing Values, Hastings Center Report (November 24, 2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Luna Z. and Luker K. Reproductive Justice. Annual Review of Law and Social Science. 2013;9(1):327–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, R. (1999). Against Relativism. Cultural Diversity and the Search for Ethical Universals in Medicine. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munson, R. (2008). "Reproductive Control." Intervention and Reflection: Basic Issues in Medical Ethics. 8th ed. Belmont, CA. 364–451

    Google Scholar 

  • Norlock, Kathryn, Feminist Ethics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2019), available at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-ethics/

  • O’Neill O (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill O. Some limits of informed consent. J Med Ethics 2003 291, available at https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1733683/pdf/v029p00004.pdf.

  • Percival, T. (1803), Medical Ethics; or a Code of Institutes and Precepts, Adapted to the Professional Interests of Physicians and Surgeons (Manchester: S. Russell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W.D. (1930, Reprinted 2007), The Right and The Good. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael (2010). Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do? Farrar, Straus and Giroux; Reprint edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scully, J., Feminist Bioethics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Rev 2015), available at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminist-bioethics/.

  • Sister Song – Reproductive Justice, https://www.sistersong.net/reproductive-justice.

  • The Oxford Handbook of Reproductive Ethics. Oxford University Press. January 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (2013). Moral Theory: An introduction (2nd ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Aljalian, N., King, L.P. (2023). Basic Primer on Principles and Philosophy Applicable to Reproductive Bioethics. In: King, L.P., Band, I.C. (eds) Case Studies in the Ethics of Assisted Reproduction. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-41215-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation