Polanyi’s Copernican Realism: Content, Reception, and Relation to Three Contemporary Realisms

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Metaphysics of Michael Polanyi
  • 43 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter examines existing interpretations of the most widely commented-upon aspect of Michael Polanyi’s metaphysics, his metaphysical realism. I argue that his position ought to be taken as a form of Copernicanism and then put his distinctive Copernican realism into conversation with contemporary approaches to metaphysical realism including Ontic Structural Realism, Object-Oriented Ontology, and neo-Aristotelian hylomorphism. This chapter thus begins to make clear the relevance of debates within Polanyi studies for the broader sphere of contemporary metaphysical exploration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
GBP 19.95
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
GBP 79.50
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
GBP 99.99
Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See for example Gulick (1999–2000), Sanders (1999–2000), and Cannon (1999–2000), all of whom attribute to Polanyi some form of metaphysical realism and explicitly deny the inherent totalitarianism of such a position.

  2. 2.

    Esther Meek, email message to the author, October 27, 2020.

  3. 3.

    Similarly, Jha notes that Polanyi “drew on a Platonic-Aristotelian kind of formism relying on the general notion of similarity. His numerous analogies are built on the notion of similarity of some features, where to explain conceptions outside of or straddling frameworks, he relies on either a series of free-standing or of overlap** analogies” (1999–2000, 20). She does not seem entirely comfortable with this aspect of his thought. With regard to the analogical element of Polanyi, Phil Mullins (email message to the author, September 1, 2020, article forthcoming) has argued that Dorothy Emmett’s work on analogy in metaphysics likely played an influential role in Polanyi’s philosophical development.

  4. 4.

    See Ladyman (1998) on whether structural realism should be taken as a metaphysical or merely epistemological proposal.

  5. 5.

    Ladyman and Ross might respond that their view of science is based on a sort of Peircean pragmatism or instrumentalism, yet Peirce is much more insightful and honest when looking at the workings of science in terms of the concrete operations of scientists. Much of this work of Peirce’s would, I believe, violate the PNC, though such an argument lies beyond the scope of this work.

  6. 6.

    I say “quasi-positivist” because given that OSR affirms the mathematical structure retained through the evolution of scientific theory as real (often treating it as interchangeable with nomological structure), and not merely a useful calculating tool, it is not positivist in a strict sense.

  7. 7.

    Scale relativity is “…the idea that which terms of description and principles of individuation we use to track the world vary with the scale at which the world is measured…Here are some […examples]: at the quantum scale there are no cats; at scales appropriate for astrophysics there are no mountains; and there are no cross-elasticities of demand in a two-person economy” (Ladyman et al. 2007, Location 3317).

  8. 8.

    This anti-reductionist stance could theoretically change with future science – it is not an a priori matter, as anti-reductionism is for Polanyi).

  9. 9.

    “The idea of structure that I have in mind is that of modal structure – nomological structure – rather than mathematical structure. However, it might be that the necessity of mathematics and the physical necessity of laws coincide, and the history of physics has progressively undermined the distinction between mathematical and physical necessity. We do not advocate Pythagoreanism or Platonism, because they contrast mathematical or formal existence with material being. Our metaphysics is directly motivated, just as we say all metaphysics should be, by the actual content of physics, and our review of the latter significantly undermines the distinction between mathematical and physical-nomological structure. However, if mathematical structure does not coincide with physical structure then the relationship between them is surely that of isomorphism (or something similar but weaker such as homomorphism).” (James Ladyman, quoted in Veal 2012, 165)

  10. 10.

    Quentin Meillasoux states “By ‘correlation’ we mean the idea according to which we only ever have access to the correlation between thinking and being, and never to either term considered apart from the other. We will henceforth call correlationism any current of thought which maintains the unsurpassable character of the correlation so defined. Consequently, it becomes possible to say that every philosophy which disavows naïve realism has become a variant of correlationism” (2006, 5).

  11. 11.

    “The affirmation of a scientific theory was seen to convey an appreciation of its beauty and all the statements of mathematics were seen to carry a whole gamut of delicate aesthetic appreciations” (PK 204).

  12. 12.

    See Chap. 2 of Simpson (2023) and Johnston (2006), pages 659–660 for a summation of key disagreements within the hylomorphist camp.

  13. 13.

    At this point I must introduce a somewhat unfortunate terminological binary that will be necessary for clarity off and on throughout the remainder of this book. The terms I refer to here are “Anti-Platonist Aristotelianism” (including references to the Aristotle of Anti-Platonist Aristotelianism) vs. a Platonist Aristotle (which gestures toward a harmonization of Plato and Aristotle similar to the Neoplatonist synthesis and which therefore, in my view, is a subspecies of Platonism). The need for this terminological hack arises due to the fact that the most prominent expositions of Aristotelianism generally take Aristotle to be in conflict with Plato, especially with respect to the question of universals and Forms, as seen in point 5, cited in the main text above. The Anti-Platonist Aristotelian position, glossed in more depth later, holds that there are no transcendent, uninstantiated universals (i.e. Platonic Forms) but is realist with respect to immanent universals which are instantiated in particular sensibles. Such an Aristotelianism will also often show a sort of ontological favoritism toward particulars (primary substance) over universals (secondary substance) which is based on Aristotle’s Categories (see also Norio Fujisawa 1974, 38–40 on such an “Aristotelian thought framework”).

    There is, of course, plenty of variety in viewpoint among those who consider themselves Aristotelians, however this is, in my estimation, a more or less fair summation of what is taken to be the Aristotelian position on universals in most mainstream debates, philosophy classes, etc. When I critique Aristotelian positions in what follows, I am generally critiquing this Anti-Platonist Aristotelianism. Interspersed throughout the book, however, (and coming more into focus in the final chapter) are references to a Platonist reading of Aristotle which takes Aristotle himself to be a Platonist interested in develo** a more rigorous understanding of matter in harmony with the central doctrines of Platonism (see Gerson 2005). On this reading, his theory of universals is taken to be an explanation of our conceptual tracking mechanism and not a rival metaphysical theory to the Forms.

  14. 14.

    While most neo-Aristotelians are realists with respect to immanent, Aristotelian universals, there are exceptions. William Jaworsky (2016), for example, is a trope theorist, and thinkers such as Koons and Simpson are moving in that direction as well (email message from W.M.R. Simpson, May 7, 2023).

  15. 15.

    Charles Lowney has also noted Polanyi’s Platonist stance on universals, especially in “The Tacit in Frege” (2008), and holds that there need be no real conflict between Aristotle and Plato on this point. I agree with him on both counts, as will be made clear in subsequent chapters.

  16. 16.

    The common understanding of “universal” either as a rough synonym for “Form” (or as a rival term for describing the metaphysical ground of entities’ natures) will be called into question in subsequent chapters. For now, however, we will stick to the standard terminology as it appears in neo-Aristotelian scholarship.

  17. 17.

    See, for instance, “Faith and Reason” 239–240, where Polanyi uses the words “thing” and “whole” interchangeably in reference to the object of our knowledge conceived of as the gestalt comprised of subsidiary details before introducing the term “comprehensive entity.” In Meaning (34–35) parallel passages use the terms “focal target” and “object of focal attention” before stating that

    The subsidiaries of from-to knowing bear on a focal target, and whatever a thing bears on may be called its meaning. Thus the focal target on which they bear is the meaning of the subsidiaries. (Ibid.)

    He goes on to equate the “complex entity” made up of subsidiaries with the “joint meaning” of those subsidiaries (M 53–54). Elsewhere (e.g. TD 13 or SOM 29), he uses “joint meaning” in nearly identical formulations.

  18. 18.

    I recognize that this claim may seem premature and unsupported to some interpreters of Polanyi. I shall argue my case soon enough.

  19. 19.

    Marmodoro has also written perceptively on certain aspects of Plato’s metaphysics (2021).

References

  • Aristotle. De Anima trans. J.A. Smith. Internet Classics Archive. Accessed September 28, 2021. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.html.

  • _____. Categories trans. E.M. Edghill. The Internet Classics Archive. Accessed March 10, 2023. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/categories.1.1.html.

  • Cannon, Dale. 1999–2000. “Some Aspects of Polanyi’s Version of Realism.” Tradition and Discovery 26/3: 51–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. 1991. “Real Patterns.” The Journal of Philosophy 88/1: 27–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Kit. 1999. “Things and Their Parts.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Vol. 23: 61–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fujisawa, Norio. 1974. “Εχειν, Μετέχειν, and Idioms of ‘Paradeigmatism’ in Plato’s Theory of Forms.” Phronesis 19/1: 30–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, Lloyd P. 2005. Aristotle and Other Platonists. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gulick, Walter B. 1999–2000. “Beyond Epistemology to Realms of Meaning.” Tradition and Discovery 26/3: 24–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. “The Meaningful and the Real in Polanyian Perspective.” Polanyiana. 8/1–2: http://www.kfki.hu/chemonet/polanyi/; http://www.ch.bme.hu/chemonet/polanyi/

  • Harman, Graham. 2002. Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects. Chicago, Il: Open Court Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. “On Vicarious Causation.” Collapse II: 187–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. “I am also of the opinion that materialism must be destroyed.” Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, Volume 28: 772 – 790.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Weird Realism: Lovecraft and Philosophy. Washington: Zero Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything. Pelican Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, William. 2016. Structure and Metaphysics of Mind: How Hylomorphism Solves the Mind-Body Problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jha, S.R. 1999–2000. “Polanyi’s Problematic ‘Man in Thought’: the Tacit and the Real – an Exploration and a Critique.” Tradition and Discovery 26/3: 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, Mark. 2006. “Hylomorphism.” The Journal of Philosophy 103/12. Special Issue: Parts and Wholes: 652–698.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, Robert C. 2014. “Staunch vs. Faint-Hearted Hylomorphism: Toward an Account of Composition.” Res Philosophica 91/2: 151–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, Kathryn. 2008. The Structure of Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James. 1998. “What is Structural Realism?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A. 29/3: 409-424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James, Ross, Don, and Collier, John G. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowney II, Charles. 2008. “The Tacit in Frege.” Polanyiana. 1-2/17: 19–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmodoro, Anna. 2013. “Aristotle’s Hylomorphism without Reconditioning.” Philosophical Inquiry 37/1–2: 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meek, Esther Lightcap. 2017. Contact with Reality: Michael Polanyi’s Realism and Why It Matters. Eugene, OR: Cascade Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meillasoux, Quentin. 2006. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Trans. Ray Brassier. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, Phil. 1999–2000. “The Real As Meaningful.” Tradition and Discovery 26/3: 42–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. “Polanyi’s Participative Realism.” Polanyiana 6/2: https://www.kfki.hu/~cheminfo/polanyi/9702/mullins.html

  • Oderberg, David S. 2005. “Hylemorphic Dualism.” Social Philosophy and Policy 22/2: 70–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1997. Sophist trans. Nicholas P. White, in Plato: Complete Works. Edited by John M. Cooper. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, Michael. 1961. “Faith and Reason.” Journal of Religion 41/4: 237–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1962 [1958]. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964 [1946]. Science, Faith, and Society. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964. “Lecture 1: The Metaphysical Reach of Science.” Duke Lectures. Delivered at Duke University, February 10, 1964. http://www.polanyisociety.org/Duke/Duke1.pdf

  • ———. 1965a. “Lecture 1: Science and Reality.” Wesleyan Lectures. Delivered at Wesleyan University, September 29, 1965. http://www.polanyisociety.org/WesleyanLectures/Weslyn-lec1%2D%2D9-29-65-searchable.pdf

  • ———. 1965b. “Lecture 3: The Creative Imagination.” Wesleyan Lectures. Delivered at Wesleyan University, October 31, 1965.http://www.polanyisociety.org/WesleyanLectures/Weslyn-lec3-10-21-65.pdf

  • ———. 1966. The Tacit Dimension. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967. “Science and Reality” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science Vol. 18, No. 3: 177–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013 [1959]. The Study of Man. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, Michael and Prosch, Harry. 1975. Meaning. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prosch, Harry. 1972 “Polanyi’s Ethics.” Ethics. 82/2: 91–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puddefoot, John C. 1993–1994 “Resonance Realism.” Tradition and Discovery 20/3: 29–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, Michael C. 2011. “Hylomorphism Reconditioned.” Philosophical Perspectives 25/1: 341–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, Andy F. 1999–2000. “Science, Religion, and Polanyi’s Comprehensive Realism.” Tradition and Discovery 26/3: 84–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, William M.R. 2023. Hylomorphism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, William M.R., Koons, Robert, and Teh, Nicholas J. 2017. Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Contemporary Science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veal, Damian. 2012. “Who’s Afraid of Scientism?: Interview with James Ladyman.” Collapse V: 135–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J., 1989. “Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?” Dialectica 43: 99–124.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Turkis II, M.E. (2024). Polanyi’s Copernican Realism: Content, Reception, and Relation to Three Contemporary Realisms. In: The Metaphysics of Michael Polanyi. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-41211-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation