Husserl and the Regions of Beings

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Transcendental Idealism and Metaphysics

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 126))

  • 107 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter proposes a most systematic assessment of the notions of region and regional ontology in Husserl’s phenomenology. Contrary to what is usually assumed, the concept of region is deemed completely irreducible to a combination of non-independent parts or moments in the sense of the Third Logical Investigation. As a consequence, the chapter makes the case for a sharp distinction between the mereology of the early Husserl (and the conception of the a priori that follows from it) and the notion of regional ontology outlined in Ideas I.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In light of these distinctions, one can appreciate (euphemistically) the naiveté of the claim: L’eidétique husserlienne repose en effet sur un équivalence entre essences et eide (Romano, 2019, 162).

  2. 2.

    On this distinction, see Lowit, 1954, 326–327.

  3. 3.

    See also Shoichet, 2013, 173 and ff.

  4. 4.

    On the contrary, it is not evident how the region is understood in Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (Heidegger, 2010a, 211; Heidegger, 1965, 218).

  5. 5.

    For the so far only systematic assessment of this passage, see the fundamental Majolino, 2015.

  6. 6.

    See Tinaburri, 2011, 118–130, on Husserl’s theory of material things in relation to Aristotle’s substance.

  7. 7.

    See also Hua XXXII, 29 and ff., where Husserl systematically mobilizes the concept of region to make sense of the relation and difference between nature and spirit. For example, Husserl talks of a “region of all regions” to refer to the macro-region “world” and its many internal regional articulations.

  8. 8.

    For the sake of our discourse in the present chapter, we will be paying attention only to the very first paragraphs of the first chapter of the Third Logical Investigation. For a more systematic assessment of the text, see De Santis, 2021a, 2021b

  9. 9.

    See Brisart, 2003, for an analysis of the development of Husserl’s view on the “abstract.”

  10. 10.

    On this, see also Plourde, 2003.

  11. 11.

    See the way in which Husserl formulates the corresponding definition in §13 of the Third Logical Investigation: “A content A is relatively non-independent in regard to a content B (or in regard to the total range of contents determined by B and all its parts), if a pure law, rooted in the peculiar character of the genus-essence of content in question, ensures that a content of the pure genus A has an a priori incapacity to obtain except in, or as associated with, other contents from the total ranges of the pure genera of contents determined by B” (Hua XIX/1, 264; Husserl, 2001, II, 22).

  12. 12.

    See Husserl’s words: “Wherever therefore the word ‘can’ occurs in conjunction with the pregnant use of ‘think,’ there is a reference, not to a subjective necessity, i.e. to the subjective incapacity-to-represent-things-otherwise, but to the objectively ideal necessity of an inability-to-be-otherwise” (Hua XIX/1, 242–243; Husserl, 2001, II, 11–12).

  13. 13.

    This is the reason why Majolino, 2015, 47, correctly speaks of “unity of being” to characterize the region.

  14. 14.

    We call it mereological according to Husserl’s attempt at accounting for the concept of moment in terms of “non-independence.” Of course, one could object to our argument that, insofar as an individuum is a whole made up of parts, the regional impossibility is in the end to be understood as a variation upon the mereological impossibility. We could of course agree, but only on condition that we admit that a new sense is being ascribed to the notion of whole. For in the case of the regional whole, the concretum is no longer composed of parts standing to one another in a non-independence-sort of relation in the same sense in which a moment of color stands in relation to a moment of extension.

  15. 15.

    See Simons, 1994, for a different perspective on the matter.

  16. 16.

    For a systematic analysis of the a priori in Husserl, which however overlooks the distinction that here we are trying to bring to the fore, see Romano, 2010, 209–249. In the field of Husserl scholarship, see Costa et al., 2002, 72 ff., who speak of “material ontology” without acknowledging the specificity of the notion of region. De Monticelli & Conni, 2008 do not include the “region” among the technical terms of phenomenology, although their approach is ontology-oriented. See by contrast Drummond, 2007, 180, who includes an entry on the notion of region.

  17. 17.

    Since here we are interested only in the concept of region in general, the reader can turn to Majolino, 2010, for a detailed analysis of Husserl’s eidetics of consciousness in Ideas. A recently published interesting text on the matter is the Beilage XLVIII in Hua XLIII/1, 498–500 (Allgemeine Wesenseigenheit eines intentionalen Erlebens).

  18. 18.

    This specific and technical aspect concerning Heidegger’s interpretation of the region has been so far overlooked by the Husserl-Heidegger scholarship; see for example Stapleton, 1983, 24–29; and the otherwise very important pages by Øverenget, 1998, 84 and ff.; Overgaard, 2004, 74 and ff. Von Herrmann, 2000, just like Greisch, 1994, does not even seem to consider the notion of “region” as an important phenomenological concept. Hopkins, 1993, 32 and ff. (more generally, the entire Chap. 2) pays a great deal of attention to the concept of region in Ideas I, and to the manner in which Heidegger critically tackles it (see 104 and ff.); yet he never seems to raise the question how Heidegger understands or misunderstands it.

  19. 19.

    See the entire text Nr. 17 in Hua XXXIV, 264–278 on the question about the sense of being in relation to Heidegger, in which Husserl re-asserts with even greater emphasis the points we are making in these pages as regards the meaning of the empty “something” and the material-ontological plurality.

  20. 20.

    For a different perspective, see Mohanty, 1970, 128–151; and Arnold, 2020 for a more recent and critical analysis of the concept of object in Husserl’s phenomenology.

  21. 21.

    For an analysis of how to understand the problem of “analogy” in Husserl in connection to its material and regional ontology, see the beautiful study by Mariani, 2012. As the reader can imagine, the discussion of the problem of analogy in Husserl goes far beyond the scope of this book and its author’s expertise. On the concept of “multiplicity” in Husserl and its importance for the theory of constitution, see Majolino, 2012.

  22. 22.

    See De Santis, 2021a, 2021b, 225 ff., on Husserl’s ontological plurality principle from the angle of the problem of the a priori.

  23. 23.

    We are of course fully aware that for Husserl “formal ontology” is a science of its own and that formal-ontological categories represent “that without which entities as such are not thinkable.” We are in this case following Spiegelberg’s interpretation of the relation between formal and material ontology, the importance of which has yet to be recognized in Husserl scholarship. In his essay of 1930, Spiegelberg understands in a quite peculiar way Husserl’s own statements from Ideas I according to which, “As what is most universal, the formal (das Formale) includes everything else not only under itself, but in a certain sense also in itself. Hence, it cannot be considered without the material (das Materiale), even though it will always remain distinct from it (von diesem immer verschieden bleibt)” (Spiegelberg, 1930, 7). For example, the formal part-whole relationship cannot be fully understood ontologically without taking into account the different meanings it can take on depending on the specific “material” essence of the entity which it characterizes. Since our ambition here is not to defend Spiegelberg’s reading of Husserl, but rather simply to suggest a possible direction, we can refer the reader to De Santis, 2014, 102–129 and ff. Up to a certain extent, Spiegelberg would argue, the very talk of formal conditions of thinkability is pointless unless one actually refers to a specific, and materially determined ontological domain. For example, as we saw above, the impossibility of thinking separately “color” and “extension” and two non-independent objects is not the same as the impossibility of thinking of an individual thing (= individuum) without also including all its material-regional determinations. This is the reason why in his text Spiegelberg invests a great deal of energy and time in distinguishing the many different species of (material) unities and wholes, hence the many different and materially determined part-whole relations. Of course, the point would be to better understand what he intends to say when he affirms that das Formale and das Materiale are verschieden, “distinct” and yet however “inseparable.” For a different Husserlian perspective, see Hopkins, 1993, 33 and ff.

  24. 24.

    In his lectures of 1928 on Leibniz, Heidegger makes a remark that seems to go precisely in the direction of Husserl and his understanding of the relation between “being” and the regional multiplicity. Here is the text: “The term ‘being’ is meant to include the span of all possible regions. But the problem of the regional multiplicity of being, if posed universally, includes an investigation into the unity of this general term ‘being’: into the way in which the general term ‘being’ varies with different regional meanings. This is the problem of the unity of the idea of being and its regional variants” (Heidegger, 1978, 192; Heidegger, 1984, 151). Now, the reference to Aristotle, hence to the problem of the unity of being vis-à-vis its regional variants, immediately tells us to what extent Heidegger’s position should not be identified with Husserl’s own view. Aristotle (and Heidegger) does not recognize any ontological instance higher than the supreme genus: hence, the “variants” Heidegger has in mind when he speaks of “regional multiplicity of being” is the generic variant and the generic multiplicity.

  25. 25.

    All ontology, no matter how rich and tightly knit a system of categories it has at its disposal, remains fundamentally blind and perverts its innermost intent if it has not previously clarified the sense of being sufficiently and grasped this clarification as its fundamental task” (Heidegger, 1967, 11; Heidegger, 2010, 12).

  26. 26.

    The term appears only in the French translation of the Sommaire des leçons du professeur E. Husserl (Hua I, 196 and 197). The two expressions are: une région de l’être et de connaissance; la région de l’Ego pur. But they do not have any correspondence in the original German text of the Inhaltsüberblick: the first appearance of the French région corresponds to the German Seinssphäre (Hua I, 189), while the second has no correspondence at all.

  27. 27.

    “the fourfold distinction of being of accident (ὂν κατὰ συμβεβεκός), being of the true (ὂν ὡς αληθές), being (ὂν) of the categories, and being as potentiality and as act (ὂν δυνάμει καὶ ἐνεργεία)” (Brentano, 1960, 7; Brentano, 1975, 3–4). For a critical reading of Heidegger’s early position vis-à-vis Brentano, see Shoichet, 2013.

  28. 28.

    For a confirmation of this reading, see the recent Antonelli & Boccaccini, 2021, 85–86 “L’impegno che Brentano profonde nel campo della psicologia empirica non si configura dunque come una deviazione dai precedenti interessi ontologici, ma si traduce nel compito di individuare in campo psicologico […] la natura dell’essere in senso proprio.”

  29. 29.

    For a historical reconstruction, see for example Raspa, 2020, 169–187 on Brentano, and 221–251 on Apelt.

  30. 30.

    On this, see van Kerckhoven, 1988, Chap. IV; and the beautiful pages by Bruzina, 2004, 463 and ff.

  31. 31.

    See Klev, 2017 on Husserl’s conception of region’s influence on Carnap and the Aufbau.

References

  • Antonelli, M., & Boccaccini, F. (2021). Franz Brentano. Mente, coscienza, realtà. Carocci Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apelt, O. (1891). Beiträge zur Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie. Druck und Verlag von B. G. Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, T. (2020). The object (s) of phenomenology. Husserl Studies, 36, 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bottani, A., & Davies, R. (Eds.). (2007). Ontologie regionali. Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1960). Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles. Georg Olms Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1973). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Erster Band. Hamburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1975). On the several senses of being in Aristotle. University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1995). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brisart, R. (2003). Le général et l’abstrait: sur la maturation des Recherches logiques. In D. Fisette & S. Lapointe (édité par), Aux origines de la phénoménologie. Husserl et le contexte des Recherches logiques (pp. 23–40). Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruzina, Ronald. 2004. Edmund Husserl & Eugen Fink. Beginnings and ends in phenomenology, 1928–1938. : Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, V., Franzini, E., & Spinicci, P. (2002). La fenomenologia. Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Libera, A. (2014). La querelle des universaux. De Platon à la fin du Moyen Âge. Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Monticelli, R., & Conni, C. (2008). Ontologia del nuovo. La rivoluzione fenomenologica e la ricerca oggi. Milano.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (Ed.). (2014). Di Idee ed essenze. Un dibattito su fenomenologia e ontologia (1921–1930), con saggi di Jean Hering, Roman Ingarden e Herbert Spiegelberg. Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2015). Once again, gigantomachy: Prolegomena to a reinterpretation of the Schlick-Husserl quarrel on the synthetic a priori. Archivio di Filosofia, 3, 161–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2021a). Husserl and the a priori. Phenomenology and rationality. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2021b). The development of Husserl’s concept of metaphysics. In H. Jacobs (Ed.), The Husserlian mind (pp. 481–493). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. (2023). Regiony, nejvyšší rody a idea fenomenologické geografie. In J. Čapek, E. Fulínová (Eds.), Myšlení konečnosti. Pavlu Koubovi 70. narozeninám (pp. 125–134). Karolinum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. (2007). Historical dictionary of Husserl’s philosophy. Scarecrow Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, E. (1988). VI. Cartesianische Meditation. Teil 1: Die Idee einer transzendentalen Methodenlehre (Hua-Dok II/1). M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greisch, J. (1994). Ontologie et temporalité. Esquisse d’une interprétation intégrale de Sein und Zeit. Paris, Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. (1942). Neue Wege der Ontologie. In N. Hartmann (Ed.), Systematische Philosophie (pp. 199–311). Stuttgart und Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1965). Kant and the problem of metaphysics. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit (GA 2). Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1978). Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz (GA 26). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1984). The metaphysical foundation of logic. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1986). Seminare (GA 15). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1994). Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (GA 17). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Four Seminars. Indiana University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2005). Introduction to phenomenological research. Indiana University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Being and time. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010a). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (1953). L’essence de la manifestation. PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (1973). The essence of manifestation. M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (1990). Phénoménologie matérielle. PUF.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (2008). Material phenomenology. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. (1921). Bemerkungen über das Wesen, die Wesenheit und die Idee. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 4, 495–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, B. C. (1993). Intentionality in Husserl and Heidegger. The problem of the original method and phenomenology. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1971). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie (Drittes Buch, Hua V). M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (Hua I). M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie (Erstes Band, Hua III/1). M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1980). Ideas for a pure phenomenology and a phenomenological philosophy. Third Book. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Unterschungen (Zweiter Teil, Hua XIX/1; XIX/2). M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984a). Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie. Vorlesungen 1906/07 (Hua XXIV). M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1988). Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre 1908–1914 (Hua XVIII). M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1993). Cartesian meditations. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1994). Randbemerkungen zu Heideggers Sein und Zeit und Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik. Husserl Studies, 11, 3–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1996). Logik und allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie. Vorlesungen 1917/18 (Hua XXX). M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1997). Psychological and transcendental phenomenology and the confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931). Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations. Volumes I, II. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001a). Natur und Geist. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1927 (Hua XXXII). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002). Urteilstheorie. Vorlesungen 1905 (Hua-Mat V). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002a). Einleitung in die Philosophie. Vorlesungen 1922/23 (Hua XXXV). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002b). Zur phänomenologischen Reduktion. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1926–1935) (Hua XXXIV). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2005). Einführung in die Phänomenologie der Erkenntnis. Vorlesung 1909 (Hua-Mat VII). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2012). Zur Lehre vom Wesen und zur Methode der eidetischen Variation (Hua XLI). Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2014). Ideas I. Hackett Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2020). Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins. Teilband I: Verstand und Gegenstand. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1909–1927) (Hua XLIII/1). Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1925). Essentiale Fragen. Ein Beitrag zum Wesensproblem. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 7, 125–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1929). Bemerkungen zum Problem “Idealismus-Realismus”. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung. Ergänzungsband: Husserl-Festschrift (pp. 159–190). Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klev, A. (2017). Husserl and Carnap on regions and formal categories. In S. Centrone (Ed.), Essays on Husserl’s logic and philosophy of mathematics (pp. 409–429). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lowit, A. (1954). Pourquoi Husserl n’est pas platonicien. Les Études Philosophiques, 3, 324–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majolino, C. (2008). Husserl and the vicissitudes of the improper. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 8, 17–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majolino, C. (2010). La partition du réel: Remarques sur l’eidos, la phantasia, l’effondrement du monde et l’être absolu de la conscience. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences. Essays in commemoration of Edmund Husserl (pp. 573–660). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Majolino, C. (2012). Multiplicity, manifolds and varieties of constitution: A manifesto. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 12, 155–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majolino, C. (2015). Individuum and region of being: On the unifying principle of Husserl’s headless ontology. In A. Staiti (Ed.), Commentary on Husserl’s ideas I (pp. 33–50). de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariani, E. (2012). Nient’altro che l’essere. Ricerche sull’analogia e la tradizione aristotelica nella fenomenologia. ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénoménologie de la perception. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1958). Phenomenology of perception. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). Le visible et l’invisible. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible. Northwestern University of Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, J. N. (1970). Phenomenology and ontology. M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Øverenget, E. (1998). Seeing the self. Heidegger on subjectivity. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S. (2004). Husserl and Heidegger on being in the world. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Patočka. (2009, January). Fenomenologické spisy II. OIKOYMENH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plourde, J. (2003). Nécessité, phénoménologie et essence dans les Recherches logiques. In D. Fisette & S. Lapointe (édité par), Aux origines de la phénoménologie. Husserl et le contexte des Recherches logiques (pp. 125–147). Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porfirio. (2004). Isagoge. In appendice la versione latina di Boezio. Milan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porphyry. (2006). Introduction. Translated with a Commentary by J. Barnes. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, V. (2020). Origine e significato delle categorie di Aristotele. Il dibattito nell’Ottocento. Quodlibet.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2010). Au Coeur de la raison, la phénoménologie. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2019). Les repères éblouissants. Renouveler la phénoménologie. Paris.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1943). L’être et le néant. Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1978). Being and nothingness. Pocket Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schell, H. (1873). Die Einheit des Seelenlebens aus den Principien der aristotelischen Philosophie entwickelt. Verlag von Franz Scheuble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoichet, A. (2013). From Brentano to Heidegger: Locating the “question of the meaning of being”. In T. Keiling (Hrsg.), Heideggers Marburger Zeit. Themen, Argumente, Konstellationen (pp. 163–175). V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (1994). Particulars in particular clothing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 553–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1930). Über das Wesen der Idee. Eine ontologische Untersuchung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 11, 1–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapleton, T. J. (1983). Husserl and Heidegger: The question of a phenomenological beginning. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2010). Einleitung in die Philosophie (ESGA 8). Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (2015). Potenz und Akt (ESGA 10). Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinaburri, E. (2011). Husserl e Aristotele. Coscienza, immaginazione, mondo. Franco Angeli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trizio, E. (2021). Philosophy’s nature: Husserl’s phenomenology, natural science and metaphysics. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Kerckhoven, G. (1988). Mondanizzazione e individuazione. La posta in gioco nella Sesta Meditazione Cartesiana. il Melangolo.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Herrmann, F. W. (2000). Hermeneutik und Reflexion. Der Begriff der Phänomenologie beig Heidegger und Husserl. Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniele De Santis .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

De Santis, D. (2023). Husserl and the Regions of Beings. In: Transcendental Idealism and Metaphysics. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 126. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39590-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation