Ontophylogenesis, Interpretation and Symmetries

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Theoretical Principles of Relational Biology

Part of the book series: Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology ((HPHST,volume 6))

  • 51 Accesses

Abstract

After introducing the concept of organization, this chapter is devoted to evolution, limiting analysis to the evolutionary interpretation of organisms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 93.08
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
EUR 117.69
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In order to deepen this way of conceiving “interpretation” from the philosophical point of view, see Marinucci and Crescenzi (2021). A new book about evolution and interpretation is a work in progress.

  2. 2.

    It is worth remembering that, from the point of view of theoretical construction, it is necessary to overcome the necessity and the idea of existence of a general invariant in order to build a new theoretical biology. From the descriptive point of view, if there are many differences in considering god, organization or DNA as biological invariant, methodologically it is exactly the same because it is a matter of extremely similar theoretical structures.

  3. 3.

    It is not trivial to remember that these are concepts and not real entities.

  4. 4.

    For an opposite position see: Huxley (1943) and Grafen (2014).

  5. 5.

    Although this concept is from Agamben (2008), it is used according to Marinucci and Crescenzi (2021). This concept is important to emphasize that the common ancestor itself is not so important, but what is relevant in it. If the loss of the kiwi’s wings is taken into account, its digestive system is an irrelevant element.

  6. 6.

    In this sense, the concept of “origin” can be considered as the secularization of theological concept of God.

  7. 7.

    This last word will be preferred. It is from Longo (2016).

  8. 8.

    In order to avoid to fall into the organicistic perspective, it is important to remember that organisms are historical-empirical a priori.

  9. 9.

    It is important to talk about “interpretation” because this binds the discourse to an immanent and contingent plan as “inter-praetium” means etymologically a negotiation, the fact of establishing the price of something between two or more people. Obviously, for each negotiation different prices are possible; similarly, in relational biology, the same elements can produce different phenotypes.

  10. 10.

    It is necessary to express in this way because one is always within an interpretation and, therefore, it is not possible to talk about essential causes for the reconstruction of a phenotype, such as Laplace or as in organicist closure of constraints. For the same reason, the points of arising are also related to a specific perspective. Therefore, an element is essential for the interpretation of a phenotype within a context and never absolutely.

  11. 11.

    The classic example of symmetry breaking is that of the iron-magnetic transition. Considering an iron bar and the same bar, but magnetized, it is easy to understand that its properties change. In particular, the group, constituting the properties of iron bar, differs from that of magnetized bar, even if some properties are maintained, such as rotation on the axis of magnetic field. It is very interesting that symmetries breaking does not necessarily imply the change of all properties, because this aspect allows to free intertextuality from any type of holism.

  12. 12.

    From the strictly mathematical point of view, this set can not be considered a “group” because it does not contain its identity, but it is found outside, in the phenotype they explain. For this reason, the more generic expression was used, “set of properties” and not “group”. Nevertheless, phenotype is and remains that with respect to which a certain group of properties is organized.

  13. 13.

    As already mentioned, similarities should not be considered as a degree of identity, but as an evidence of variation. This does not mean that common aspect remains important.

  14. 14.

    The concept of “deformation” comes directly from the fact that relational space derives from general relativity, mutatis mutandis. Now, if a mass is inserted inside the space, curvature tensor changes and space changes too(relations among masses). In biology, the deformation of interpretive field means enabling something having effects on phenotypes. Obviously, it would be necessary to consider the differences between physical and biological relational space. This topic will be dealt with in another text.

Bibliography

  • Agamben, Giorgio. 2008. Signatura rerum. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailly, Francis, and Giuseppe Longo. 2006. Mathématiques et sciences de la nature. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buiatti, Marcello, and Giuseppe Longo. 2013. Randomness and multi-level interactions in biology. Theory if Biosciences 132(3): 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen, Alan. 2014. The formal Darwinism project in outline. Biology & Philosophy 29: 155–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, Julian. 1943. Evolution, the Modern Synthesis. New York - London: Harper and Brothers Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, François. 1970. La logique du vivant. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, Giuseppe. 2016. Comment le future dépend du passé et des événements rares dans le systèmes du vivant. In La liberté de l’improbable, ed. Berthoz and Ossola. Collège de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marinucci, Angelo, and Luca Crescenzi. 2021. Intertestualità. Testo e mondo a partire dalle variazioni. Pisa: ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod, Jacques. 1989. Le hasard et la nécessité. Paris: France loisir.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, Maël. 2022. Historicity at the heart of biology. Theory in Biosciences 141: 165–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tapp, Kristopher. 2012. Simetry. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, Mary Jane. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, Mary Jane. 2005. Developmental plasticity and the origin of species differences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 102(1): 6543–6549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2001. Pensieri diversi. Adelphi: Milano.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Marinucci, A. (2023). Ontophylogenesis, Interpretation and Symmetries. In: Theoretical Principles of Relational Biology. Human Perspectives in Health Sciences and Technology, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39374-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation