Structural Assemblies and Semantics of the Four Existential Constructions with Relative Clause

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Specificational and Presentational There-Clefts

Abstract

This chapter analyses the structural assemblies and semantics of the four existential constructions with relative clause. A simple existential clause codes a relation of occurrence hosted by the setting indexed by existential there. If the NP with existent role contains a restrictive relative clause, then the occurrence relation is construed as quantifying the instances of the composite type specifications of this NP. Non-restrictive relative clauses are either appositional to the existent NP or hypotactic to the main clause. In there-clefts, existential be is a three-place predicate, with existential there its subject, the existent NP its direct complement and the relative clause its indirect complement. In specificational there-clefts, the matrix codes the cognitive state resulting from an implied specificational act. The direct complement quantifies, or refers to, instances that match the definition in the relative clause. In presentational there-clefts, the matrix presents an entity, on which the relative clause predicates a discourse-new situation within the speaker’s cognitive awareness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 32.09
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
EUR 42.79
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In accordance with our natural grammar tenet, we take it that the construal of the setting as subject, e.g. tanker Braer in (82a) has a different semantic effect from its construal as adjunct, e.g. from the storage tank in (82b). A possible semantic-pragmatic motivation was proposed by Vandenberghe (1998). He argues that in examples like (82a) the subject coding conveys a non-agentive notion of ‘responsibility’, such as a structural weakness or technical fault of the entity.

  2. 2.

    Whilst Smith’s studies focus on German existential es, they also support the setting-subject analysis of English existential there.

  3. 3.

    In Dutch and French existential clauses like (ia) and (ib), the semantic components of type specifications and quantified instantiation are clearly expressed by separate constituents. The pronoun er in Dutch (ia) and en in French (ib) mean ‘of that type’: they give instructions to anaphorically retrieve the relevant type specifications from the preceding text. Er and en function as adjunct of the existent NPs which themselves consist only of a quantifier, ‘three’, which quantifies the instantiation of the retrieved type. On Dutch er followed by quantifier, see Kruisinga (1949, § 294.a), Bech (1952: 26–32). On French en followed by quantifier, see Grevisse and Goosse (2011: 914).

    1. (i)

      a. Zijn er valide argumenten voor deze positie? Ja, er zijn er drie.

      b. Est-ce qu’il y a des arguments valides pour cette position? Oui, il y en a trois.

      “Are there valid arguments for this position? Yes, there are ‘of that type’ three”.

  4. 4.

    In (90), the final relative clause is a cleft relative clause, as shown by its ability to have Ø subject relative marker: there was a man who was the head of the Irish Museum [Ø] was a German spy. This presentational there-cleft opens a set of stories about appointments of Germans before and during the war.

  5. 5.

    The supplement relation awaits further elucidation within a cognitive-functional framework, which is, however, beyond the scope of this study.

  6. 6.

    It is intriguing that Halliday (1967a) and Bolinger (1977) posit a form-meaning mismatch for clefts in spite of their theoretical commitment to a natural coding relation between grammar and semantics.

  7. 7.

    Against the traditional analysis that views the relative clause in pseudo-clefts as a restrictive relative clause, we view it as a relative clause that has a full NP as antecedent. In footnote 12 in Chapter 7, we point out that the relative clause in pseudo-clefts also allows the zero subject relative, e.g. The one thing Ø gives me a happy feeling … is that he’s going to be shewn up (Golding, Lord: 142, quoted in Erdmann, 1980: 142).

  8. 8.

    Deictic constructions with a finite relative clause as in (103) are judged acceptable by native speakers, but in actual usage English deictic constructions overwhelmingly take non-finite participial clauses, as in the original example from LLC, ^there was my auntie /Elsie // sitting on the sett\/ee // kn\itting //, from which we derived (104).

  9. 9.

    Which, as we will argue below, also applies to indefinite NPs.

  10. 10.

    They have what Declerck (1988) refers to as the descriptionally-identifying reading, in which an already identified subject is backed up with further information in the complement.

  11. 11.

    For recognition criteria distinguishing clefts with specificational relative clause from constructions containing an NP-internal restrictive relative clause, we refer to Sect. 6. (113) is an it-cleft, as it answers the implied question Who wins? – Nobody wins. By contrast, an example with restrictive relative clause like I am seeing someone, but it's no one that you've ever met does not answer the implied question Which people have I ever met? – You have met no one ever. In (115), speaker A uses a there-cleft, in which the specificational relative clause features the distinctive formal characteristic of zero relative with subject function, there’s a lot of people ø do call it a road. Speaker B retorts with an opaque verb-cleft containing the same variable expressed by a specificational relative clause with overt subject relative marker but a negative value, I’ve found nobody that calls it that.

  12. 12.

    Doherty (1993), like other studies of the zero subject relative marker such as Erdmann (1980) and Haegeman et al. (2015: 62), notes that it is also attested in pseudo-clefts like You were the one Ø came in. As just recapitulated, we follow Donnellan (1966) in attributing a definitional reading to the relative clause in pseudo-clefts, just like we do to the relative clause in specificational clefts. This goes some way towards solving the distributional puzzle of relative clauses allowing zero subject relative markers. Relative clauses whose paradigm of relative markers includes the zero subject relative have definitional meaning in specificational constructions. However, zero relatives also occur in presentational clefts, which shows that a broader semantic generalization must be formulated to cover their complete distribution.

  13. 13.

    In Chapter 9, we discuss examples in our data with this information structure.

  14. 14.

    Delin (1992) correctly stressed that the matrix of it-clefts describes a state, which is asserted in a declarative cleft and inquired into in an interrogative cleft.

  15. 15.

    Example (122) is a quantifying there-cleft whose value NP has a negative quantifier and contains a restrictive relative clause and whose specificational relative clause contains a negation as well, as in (71) There’s nothing that they consider that they do not adjourn (LLC). We thank An Van linden (p.c.) for her translation of (122).

  16. 16.

    Sisha-Halevy’s (2016) discussion of clefts in Modern Welsh does not systematically distinguish specificational from presentational clefts, but he makes the important point that clefts frequently occur in free indirect speech, where their conceptualizer is not the actual speaker.

  17. 17.

    WordbanksOnline uses MX and FX to anonymize male and female proper names.

  18. 18.

    Thus, of all types of specificational clefts, only clefts with identifying matrix trigger an exhaustiveness implicature due to the presence of the subjects it/that. The other types do not have implicatures of either exhaustiveness or non-exhaustiveness as no trigger of either is present. By contrast, specificational copulars and pseudo-clefts do offer a choice between exhaustiveness implicature and non-exhaustiveness implicature, the former triggered by a definite determiner in the variable NP and the latter by an indefinite determiner in the variable NP (see Sect. “Specificational Copular Clauses”).

  19. 19.

    Textual retrievability is a precondition but not a sufficient reason for informationally presupposing the variable from the preceding text. Speakers may use a non-reduced cleft even if the relative clause is fully discourse-given and retrievable (Bourgoin, O’Grady & Davidse, 2021).

  20. 20.

    This is a modified variant of the attested (WB) example On the train coming up, there was Roy Hatterson with a group of people.

  21. 21.

    We reject Lambrecht’s (2002) claim that the bi-clausal syntax of presentational there- and have-clefts non-compositionally codes the information structure of a topic-focus relation, in which the topic is also itself the focus of the matrix clause. For examples of zero subject contact relatives, whose matrix contains verbs like know and meet, Haegeman et al. (2015) consider but reject the idea that they express a topic-comment structure. Haegeman et al. (2015) do not distinguish the specificational from the predicative readings of these constructions.

References

  • Akmajian, A. ([1973] 1979). Aspects of the grammar of focus in English. PhD thesis, MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. ([1952–1953] 1970). Philosophical papers. In J.O. Urmson & G.J. Warnock (Eds.), Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bech, G. ([1952]1968). Über das niederländische Adverbialpronomen er. In J. Hoogteijling (Ed.), Taalkunde in artikelen. Een verzameling artikelen over het Nederlands (pp. 147–174). Wolters-Noordhoff, Groningen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, D. (1973). Ambient it is meaningful too! Journal of Linguistics, 9(2), 261–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, D. (1977). Meaning and form. Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourgoin, C., O’Grady, G., & Davidse, K. (2021). Managing information flow through prosody in it-clefts. English Language & Linguistics, 25(3), 485–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breivik, L. (1989). On the causes of syntactic change in English. In L. Breivik et al. (Eds.), Language change: Contributions to the study of its causes (pp. 29–70). Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P. (1992). Cleft existentials in English. Language Sciences, 14, 419–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P. (2006). It-clefts and wh-clefts: Prosody and pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics, 38, 1706–1720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (1992). Existential constructions: A systemic perspective. Leuven Contributions in Linguistics and Philology, 81, 71–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (1998). Agnates, verb classes and the meaning of construals: The case of ditransitivity in English. Leuvense Bijdragen, 87(3), 281–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (1999a). The semantics of cardinal versus enumerative existential constructions. Cognitive Linguistics, 10, 203–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (2000). A constructional approach to clefts. Linguistics, 38(6), 1101–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (2004). The interaction of quantification and identification in English determiners. In M. Achard & S. Kemmer (Eds.), Language, culture and mind (pp. 507–533). CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (2020). The ideational semantics of the canonical existential clause in English. In G. Tucker, G. Huang, L. Fontaine, E. McDonald (Eds.), Approaches to Systemic Functional Grammar. Convergence and divergence (pp. 293–312). Equinox.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. (2022). Refining and re-defining secondary determiners in relation to primary determiners. In L. Sommerer & E. Keizer (Eds.), English noun phrases from a functional-cognitive perspective. Current issues (pp. 27–78). John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K., & Kimps, D. (2016). Specificational there-clefts: Functional structure and information structure. English Text Construction, 9(1), 115–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidse, K. & Van Praet, W. (2019). Rethinking predicative clauses with indefinite predicate and specificational clauses with indefinite variable: A cognitive-functional account. Leuven Working Papers in Linguistics, 6(38).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, E. (2016). Construction telling: Modes of subject-predicate bonding and directions of travel in the English clause. Paper presented at the Second Round Table on Communicative Dynamism. University of Namur. September 13–14, 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, E. (2018). Construction telling: Modes of subject-predicate bonding and directions of travel in the English clause. Typescript.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cesare, A.-M., & Garassino, D. (2015). On the status of exhaustiveness in cleft sentences: An empirical and cross-linguistic study of English also-/only-clefts and Italian anche-/solo-clefts. Folia Linguistica, 49(1), 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Declerck, R. (1988). Studies on copular sentences, clefts, and pseudo-clefts. Leuven University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Declerck, R., & Seki, S. (1990). Premodified reduced it-clefts. Lingua, 82(1), 15–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delin, J. (1992). Properties of it-cleft presupposition. Journal of Semantics, 9, 289–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diessel, H. (2012). Bühler’s two-field theory of pointing and naming and the deictic origins of grammatical morphemes. In K. Davidse, et al. (Eds.), Grammaticalization and language change. New reflections (pp. 37–50). Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doherty, C. (1993). The syntax of subject contact relatives. In K. Beals et al. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 29th Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society (pp. 55–65). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75(3), 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, S., & Haden, R. (1991). A celebration of Ozark English: A collection of articles from the Lonesome Node–1980 to 1990. OCLS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erdmann, P. (1980). On the history of subject contact-clauses in English. Folia Linguistica Historica, 14, 3139–3170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grevisse, M., & Goosse, A. (2011). Le bon usagegrammaire française. 15e édition. Paris: De Boeck – Duculot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, Vol. 3 (pp. 22–40). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haegeman, L., Weir, A., Danckaert, L., D’Hulster, T., & Buelens, L. (2015). Against the root analysis of subject contact relatives in English. Lingua, 163, 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, M. A. K. (1967a). Notes on transitivity and theme in English: Part 2. Journal of Linguistics, 3(2), 199–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, M. A. K. (1985). An introduction to Functional Grammar (1st ed.). Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, M. A. K. (1994). An introduction to Functional Grammar (2nd ed.). Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English. Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, J. (1978). Definiteness and indefiniteness: A study in reference and grammaticality prediction. Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedberg, N. (2000). The referential status of clefts. Language, 76(4), 891–920.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, A. (1995). Belfast English and Standard English: Dialect variation and parameter setting. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, F. (1973). The pseudo-cleft construction in English. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1981). Exhaustiveness and the semantics of clefts. Proceedings of the 11th North East Linguistics Society (NELS), 11, 125–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, R. (1984). Introduction to the grammar of English. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, R., & Pullum, G. (2002). The Cambridge grammar of the English language. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. (2001). Constructional grounding. On the relation between deictic and existential there-constructions in first language acquisition. In A. Cienki, B. Luka, & M. Smith (Eds.), Conceptual and discourse factors in linguistic structure (pp. 123–136). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaltenböck, G. (2023). On the use of there-clefts with zero-subject relativizer. In C. Gentens, L. Ghesquière, W. McGregor, & A. Van linden (eds). Reconnecting form and meaning. In honour of Kristin Davidse (pp. 17–43). Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karssenberg, L. (2018). Non-prototypical clefts in French: A corpus analysis of “il y a” clefts. De Gruyter Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • König, J. P. & Lambrecht, K. (1999). French relative clauses as secondary predicates: A case study in Construction Theory. In F. Corblin, C. Dobrovie-Sorin, & J.-M. Carmen Marandin (Eds.), Empirical issues in formal syntax and semantics 2 (pp. 191–214). Thesus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruisinga, E. (1949). A handbook of Present-day English. Noordhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (1986). Pragmatically motivated syntax. Presentational cleft constructions in spoken French. In 22nd Conference of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Papers from the Parasession on Pragmatics and Grammatical Theory (pp. 115–126). Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (1988a). There was a farmer had a dog: Syntactic amalgams revisited. In Proceedings of the 14th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (pp. 319–339). Berkeley Linguistics Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (1988b). Presentational cleft constructions in spoken French. In J. Haiman & S. Thompson (Eds.), Clause combining in grammar and discourse (pp. 135–179). Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (1994). Information structure and sentence form. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (2001). A framework for the analysis of cleft constructions. Linguistics, 39, 463–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambrecht, K. (2002). Topic, focus and secondary predication: The French presentational relative construction. In C. Beyssade, R. Bok-Bennema, F. Drijkoningen, & P. Monachesi (Eds.), Romance languages and linguistic theory 2000: Selected papers from ‘Going Romance’ 2000, Utrecht, 30 November–2 December (pp. 171–212). Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar. Vol. 1, Theoretical preliminaries. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (1991). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar. Vol. 2, Descriptive application. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (2002). Deixis and subjectivity. In F. Brisard (Ed.), Grounding: The epistemic footing of deixis and reference (pp. 1–27). Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (2004). Remarks on nominal grounding. Functions of Language, 11(1), 77–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (2016). Nominal grounding and English quantifiers. Cognitive Linguistic Studies, 3, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (2017). Grounding, semantic functions, and absolute quantifiers. English Text Construction, 10(2), 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Léard, J.-M. (1992). Les gallicismes. Étude syntaxique et sémantique. Duculot.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lopéz-Couso, M. J. (2010). Developmental parallels in diachronic and ontogenetic grammaticalization: Existential there as a test case. Folia Linguistica, 51(1), 81–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, C. (1999). Definiteness. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGregor, W. (1997). Semiotic Grammar. Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L. (1998). Existential sentences without existential quantification. Linguistics and Philosophy, 21, 353–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, L. (2005). Copular clauses: Specification, predication and equation. Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, B. (1985). Old English syntax. Volume I: Concord, the parts of speech, and the sentence. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, J. (1978). Secondary predicates. Proceedings of the 4th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, 4, 114–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patten, A. (2012). The English it-cleft: A constructional account and a diachronic investigation. Mouton de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Percus, O. (1977). Prying open the cleft. Proceedings of the 7th North East Linguistics Society (NELS), 28, 337–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prince, E. (1992). The ZPG letter: Subjects, definiteness, and information-status. In S. Thompson & W. Mann (Eds.), Discourse description: Diverse analyses of a fundraising text (pp. 95–325). Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, M. (2011). The syntactic structure of English clefts. Lingua, 121(2), 142–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwenter, S. A., & Waltereit, R. (2010). Presupposition accommodation and language change. In K. Davidse, L. Vandelanotte, & H. Cuyckens (Eds.), Subjectification, intersubjectification and grammaticalization (pp. 76–102). de Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sisha-Halevy, A. (2016). Work notes on modern Welsh narrative syntax (II): Presentatives in narrative. Journal of Celtic Linguistics, 17, 97–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1985). An analysis of German dummy subject constructions in Cognitive Grammar. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Pacific Linguistics Conference, 1, 412–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2002). The polysemy of German es, iconicity, and the notion of conceptual distance. Cognitive Linguistics, 13(1), 67–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2005). The conceptual structure of German impersonal constructions. Journal of Germanic Linguistics, 17(2), 79–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vandenberghe, W. (1998). Force dynamic research on ‘new’ types of agency [M.A. thesis. Linguistics Department, University of Leuven].

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Eynde, F., & Jong-Bok, K. (2016). Loose apposition: A construction-based analysis. Functions of Language, 23(1), 17–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Praet, W. (2022). Specificational and predicative clauses. A functional-cognitive account. De Gruyter Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, G., & Birner, B. (1995). Definiteness and the English existential. Language, 71, 722–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, A., et al. (2000). Null subjects in Middle English existentials. In S. Pintzuk (Ed.), Diachronic syntax: Models and mechanisms (pp. 164–187). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram, W. & Christian, D. (1976). Appalachian speech. Center for Applied Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, T. (2006). Monotonicity in opaque verbs. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29(6), 715–761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristin Davidse .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Davidse, K., Njende, N.M., O’Grady, G. (2023). Structural Assemblies and Semantics of the Four Existential Constructions with Relative Clause. In: Specificational and Presentational There-Clefts. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-32270-9_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-32270-9_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-32269-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-32270-9

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation