Bioethical Decision Making and Genome Editing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Bioethical Decisions. Volume I

Part of the book series: Collaborative Bioethics ((CB,volume 2))

  • 672 Accesses

Abstract

Changing the genetic makeup of living beings is expected to transform several fields of biomedicine giving rise to a number of ethical challenges including in therapy and reproductive procedures. Against this background, however, it is important to determine whether a non-heritable (somatic) procedure is taking place, which may be comparable to conventional therapy, or whether the procedure generates a heritable genetic modification which may give rise to the selection or deselection of possible future children. In this last case, the following ethical choices may then be considered. First, individuals and society may choose to believe that all lives are equal in worth and value, making any selection and classification between possible future children meaningless. Secondly, individuals and society may believe that all possible future children are equal in value but choose not to bring a certain kind of child into existence because they recognise that they themselves or society lack the necessary support and/or capacity to look after such a child. Finally, individuals and society may decide not to bring a certain kind of child into existence, because the value of his or her life is considered to be unacceptable even though they have the resources and support necessary to look after such a child. If this last choice is accepted, however, it would also mean sanctioning selective eugenic decisions between possible future children.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Clustered regularly-interspaced short palindromic repeats with the Cas 9 protein system.

  2. 2.

    For a review of possible applications, see: Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 2018, 32–43 and WHO, 2021.

  3. 3.

    For further discussion, see for example Schechtman, 1996, Schermer, 2011, Foresight Future Identities, 2013, pp. 9–10, De Grazia, 2012, pp.70–73 and MacKellar, 2019.

  4. 4.

    This reflects an ‘animalism’ perspective which was developed, amongst others, by Paul F. Snowdon, see Snowdon, 1990. For a discussion see Olson, 2003 and Snowdon, 2014.

  5. 5.

    This reflects a ‘psychologically interconnected’ perspective. See for example Lewis, 1976. Such a psychologically interconnection would not exist, for example, between an early embryo and an adult human being since the latter would not be able to remember being an embryo.

  6. 6.

    Even conjoined twins can be considered as distinct if they each experience their own specific identity.

  7. 7.

    Somatic genome editing may be able to address specific cell types or tissues but may not be appropriate for treating other genetic disorders affecting a number of different tissues because targeting all the tissue may be difficult, National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine, 2017, 88.

  8. 8.

    For a review see: National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine, 2017 and 2020; Baylis, 2019; Evans, 2020; Parens & Johnson, 2019; WHO, 2021.

  9. 9.

    Sir Winston Churchill, wartime Prime Minister of the UK, was openly disappointed when Britain resisted eugenic action on the grounds of civil liberties. In 1910, he wrote to the then UK Prime Minister expressing his support for legislation that proposed to introduce a compulsory sterilization program in the UK saying: “The unnatural and increasingly rapid growth of the feeble-minded and insane classes, coupled as it is with a steady restriction among all the thrifty, energetic and superior stocks, constitutes a national and race danger which it is impossible to exaggerate.... I feel that the source from which the stream of madness is fed should be cut off and sealed up before another year has passed.” Quoted in Amy Iggulden, “The Churchill You Didn’t Know,” The Guardian, 27 November 2002.

  10. 10.

    For example, American Nobel Prize Laureate and co-discoverer of the structure of the DNA molecule James Watson wrote: “But diabolical as Hitler was, and I don’t want to minimize the evil he perpetuated using false genetic arguments, we should not be held in hostage to his awful past. For the genetic dice will continue to inflict cruel fates on all too many individuals and their families who do not deserve this damnation. Decency demands that someone must rescue them from genetic hells. If we don’t play God, who will?” (Watson, 1995).

  11. 11.

    For clear evidence of the feeling of offence being taken by persons with disability in a similar situation, see the disability witnesses in the prominent French court case of Nicolas Peruche. Public Hearings of the French Senate on the 18th of December 2001 relating to the jurisprudence of the ‘Perruche’ case.

  12. 12.

    The term a “life unworthy of life” (in German “Lebensunwertes Leben”) first occurred in the title of a book by German psychiatrist Alfred Hoche and lawyer Karl Binding, Die Freigabe der Vernichtung Lebensunwerten Lebens, (Leipzig: Verlag von Felix Meiner, 1920).

References

  • Andorno, R. (2010). Fondements philosophiques et culturels de l’eugénisme sélectif. In J. Laffitte & I. Carrasco de Paula (Eds.), La génétique, au risque de l’eugénisme? (pp. 129–141). Edifa-Mame.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baylis, F. (2019). Altered inheritance: CRISPR and the ethics of human genome editing. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. (2000, December 18). Official journal of the European communities, C 364/1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cong, L., et al. (2013). Multiplex genome engineering using CRISPR/Cas systems. Science, 339(6121), 819–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Council of Europe (a). (1997). Convention for the protection of human rights and dignity of the human being with regard to the application of biology and medicine, European treaty series no. 164, 4.IV (Oviedo, 1997): Article 13

    Google Scholar 

  • Council of Europe (b). (1997). Explanatory report to the convention for the protection of human rights and dignity of the human being with regard to the application of biology and medicine: Convention on human rights and biomedicine, European treaty series no. 164, 4.IV (Oviedo, 1997): Paragraph 91

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyranoski, D., & Ledford, H. (2018). Genome-edited baby claim provokes international outcry. Nature, 563, 607–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Grazia, D. (2012). Creation ethics: reproduction, genetics, and quality of life. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. H. (2020). The human gene editing debate. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foresight Future Identities. (2013). Final project report. The Government Office for Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavaghan, C. (2007). Defending the genetic supermarket: law and ethics of selecting the next generation (pp. 113–114). Routledge-Cavendish.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Iggulden, A. (2002, November 27). The Churchill you didn’t know. The Guardian. https://www.theguardian.com/theguardian/2002/nov/28/features11.g21. Accessed 21 Oct 2018.

  • **ek, M., et al. (2012). A programmable dual-RNA-guided DNA endonuclease in adaptive bacterial immunity. Science, 337(6096), 816–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kang, X., et al. (2016). Introducing precise genetic modifications into human 3PN embryos by CRISPR/Cas-mediated genome editing. Journal of Assisted Reproduction & Genetics, 33(5), 581–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirtley, M. (2016). CRISPR update: considerations for a rapidly evolving and transformative technology. Dignitas, 23(1), 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976). Survival and identity. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons. (Reprinted in his philosophical papers vol. I. 1983, Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Liang, P., et al. (2015). CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human Tripronuclear zygotes. Protein Cell, 6(5), 363–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ma, H., et al. (2017). Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in human embryos. Nature, 548(7668), 413–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKellar, C. (2019). Genome modifying reproductive procedures and their effects on numerical identity. The New Bioethics, 25(2), 121–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKellar, C. (2021). Why human germline genome editing is incompatible with equality in an inclusive society. The New Bioethics, 27(1), 19–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKellar, C., & Bechtel, C. (Eds.). (2014). The ethics of the new eugenics. Berghahn Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2005). Preventing the existence of people with disabilities. In D. Wasserman, J. Bickenbach, & R. Wachbroit (Eds.), Quality of life and human difference (pp. 142–171). Cambridge University Press. p. 154.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. (2017). Human genome editing: Science, ethics, and governance. The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. (2020). Heritable human genome editing. The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuffield Council on Bioethics. (2018). Genome editing and human reproduction: Social and ethical issues. Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. T. (2003). An argument for animalism. In R. Martin & J. Barresi (Eds.), Personal identity, Blackwell readings in philosophy (pp. 318–334). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ossorio, P. N. (2003). Inheritable genetic modifications: Do we owe them to our children? In A. R. Chapman & M. S. Frankel (Eds.), Designing our descendants: The promises and perils of genetic modification (pp. 259–262). Johns Hopkins University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parens, E., & Johnson, J. (Eds.). (2019). Human flourishing in an age of gene editing. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinders, H. S. (2000). The future of the disabled in Liberal society (p. 8). University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sas, D. F., & Lawrenz, H. M. (2017). CRISPR-Cas9: The latest fashion in designer babies. Ethics & Medicine, 33(2), 85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (1996). The constitution of selves. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schermer, M. (2011). Ethical issues in deep brain stimulation. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 5(17).

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. F. (1990). Persons, animals, and ourselves. In C. Gill (Ed.), The person and the human mind: Issues in ancient and modern philosophy (pp. 83–107). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. F. (2014). Persons, Animals, ourselves. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tang, L., et al. (2017). CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human zygotes using Cas9 protein. Molecular Genetics and Genomics, 292(3), 525–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The President’s Council on Bioethics. (2003). Beyond therapy: biotechnology and the pursuit of happiness. The President’s Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turocy, J., Adashi, E. Y., & Egli, D. (2021). Heritable human genome editing: research progress, ethical considerations, and hurdles to clinical practice. Cell, 184(6), 1561–1574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • UN General Assembly. (1948). Universal declaration of human rights, 217 (III) A (Paris, 1948), Article 1, http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/. Accessed 21 Oct 2018

  • United Nation’s Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). (1997, November 11). The universal declaration on the human genome and human rights. The following year, the United Nations General Assembly endorsed the Declaration

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nation’s Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) International Bioethics Committee. (2015, October 2). Report of the IBC on updating its reflection on the human genome and human rights, SHS/YES/IBC-22/15/2 REV.2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. (1995). Values from Chicago upbringing. In D. A. Chambers (Ed.), Deoxyribonucleic acid: The double helix—perspective and prospective at forty years (Vol. 758, p. 197). New York Academy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • WHO Expert Advisory Committee on Develo** Global Standards for Governance and Oversight of Human Genome Editing. (2021). Human genome editing: a framework for governance. World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winblad, N., & Lanner, F. (2017). Biotechnology: At the heart of gene edits in human embryos. Nature, 548(7668), 398–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Calum MacKellar .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

MacKellar, C. (2023). Bioethical Decision Making and Genome Editing. In: Valdés, E., Lecaros, J.A. (eds) Handbook of Bioethical Decisions. Volume I. Collaborative Bioethics, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-29451-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation