Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((EVBE,volume 53))

Abstract

Stakeholder theory has become one of the most important developments in the field of business ethics. While this concept has evolved and gained prominence as a method of integrating ethics into the basic purposes and strategic objectives of the firm, the authors argue that stakeholder theory has retained certain “masculinist” assumptions from the wider business literature that limit its usefulness. The resources of feminist thought, specifically the work of Carol Gilligan, provide a means of reinterpreting the stakeholder concept in a way that overcomes many of the existing limitations. This reading provides a different understanding of the identity and meaning of the firm, specifically in terms of its relationship to stakeholder groups and what it means for a firm to succeed. The alternatives proposed also converge with recent trends in the wider management literature and provide practical guidance for firms which face a myriad of challenges in the increasingly complex and global marketplace.

Originally published in: Business Ethics Quarterly, 4(4), 475–497 © Cambridge University Press, 1994

Reprint by Springer, DOI 10.2307/3857345

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (France)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 93.08
Price includes VAT (France)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
EUR 116.04
Price includes VAT (France)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Richard Rorty’s writings on pragmatism for the best and most detailed version of this approach, particularly his discussion of the ironist in Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989). Rorty maintains that language and metaphors are far more powerful in sha** our sense of “rationality” than any analytic conceptions of “reason” or logic. Indeed, he suggest that it is through new and innovative ways of speaking that we can alter the “logical space of reasons” to include the descriptions and metaphors of oppressed groups in a way that make “sense”—he cites the work of feminist thinkers who were able to sensitize us to problems like marital rape, spousal abuse, abortion rights, and the problems of pornography through stretching the boundaries of language and offering potent new metaphors. For this latter argument, see his essay “Feminism and Pragmatism” in Michigan Quarterly Review 30 (Spring 1991): 231–58.

  2. 2.

    We will not provide evidence or sustained argument about whether stakeholder theory, and this particular formulation of it, is consistent with financial success. Others, including Peters in his collaborative projects on excellence, have made this type of argument. We can also look to particular companies which adopt forms of stakeholder management—either implicitly or explicitly—as an indication that this is a reasonable conclusion [e.g., The Body Shop, Ben & Jerry’s, Coming, Johnson & Johnson, Merck, etc.] For the purpose of this paper, we want to leave open the possibility that stakeholder companies can be financially successful in the traditional sense.

  3. 3.

    In the process of offering a new set of metaphors and an alternative discourse we will create a frame of reference within which the terms business and ethics can constructively interact and reinforce each other. Stakeholder theory gives us a means of reinterpreting traditional business discourse so that ethics can have a viable place. Our feminist reinterpretation takes this project a step further and advances the attempt to make ethics and business more interconnected and pleonasmic.

  4. 4.

    Many have argued that the kinds of discourse we call “feminist” are more prevalent in most women (what Gilligan calls the “care perspective”) while “masculine” discourse is more prominent in men (what Gilligan calls the “justice perspective”).

  5. 5.

    The care orientation makes the human capacity to extend care the touchstone of moral activity. Justice places notions of rights and the capacity to logically reason with abstract moral concepts as the key to moral reflection. Care emphasizes the importance of human interaction and the ability to flourish in a network of relationships. Justice makes the individual primary and focuses on a system of rules and responsibilities that enable people to live together and respect each others’ projects. For a more complete description of the terms care and justice, see Gilligan’s work. While these terms provide an important backdrop for our argument, we will focus on the terms “masculinist” and “feminist” in the paper.

  6. 6.

    See Peter French, “The Corporation as a Moral Person,” American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1979): 207–15.

  7. 7.

    This view finds a classic articulation in Alfred P. Sloan, Jr. as related in his autobiography. My Years With GM (NY: Doubleday, 1963). While Sloan’s views about the autonomous nature of the corporation are characteristic of his era, they would fit in well with much of the strategy literature in the 1990s.

  8. 8.

    See also Michael Porter’s writings, especially Chaps. 4 & 5 of his book Competitive Strategy (Free Press, 1985), for use of military metaphors of strategy that are in this vein. A similar sense of hostility towards the external environment and the need to control it are characteristic of his views.

  9. 9.

    Mason and Mitroff as well as O’Toole can be seen as clear descendants of James March and Herbert Simon in terms of their views of the organization. For them, at bottom, the study of the organization revolves around the problem of information processing which, in turn, dictates the need for hierarchical control mechanisms.

  10. 10.

    While we argue that these metaphors are rampant in the literature on business and in our culture and we present evidence to support this claim, we do not maintain that they are universally held or that there are not serious challenges to these views on grounds similar to the arguments we make in this paper.

  11. 11.

    A number of other authors take a similar view from a non-feminist perspective. See Alisdair Maclntyre, Michael Sandel, Stanley Hauerwas, Charles Taylor and others who have been grouped under the broad category of “communitarians.”

  12. 12.

    Astley and Fombrun, like many of the other thinkers we draw from in this paper, are not “care” oriented thinkers. There are important affinities between their work and the account we are offering of stakeholder theory, but Tom Peters, Jack Welch, the Club of Rome, and other figures we cite are not necessarily “caring” individuals nor do they write from a “care” perspective. However, their insights are valuable and lend support to our view as we construct the larger narrative of the paper.

  13. 13.

    The position we take here on strategy has important affinities with the work of Gilbert—particularly his account of strategy through convention—in his book The Twilight of Corporate Strategy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).

  14. 14.

    See also Marilyn Friedman, “The Impracticality of Impartiality,” Journal of Philosophy LXXVI (1989): 645–56.

  15. 15.

    See Ed Freeman’s Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach (Boston: Pittman, 1984) for a discussion for a model of negotiation among stakeholders that is similar to what we advocate here, particularly his level three negotiation.

References

  • Ackoff, Russell. 1974. Redesigning the Future. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich, H. 1979. Organizations and Environments. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Astley, W.G., and C.J. Fombrun. 1983. Collective Strategy: Social Ecology of Organizational Environments. Academy of Management Review 8: 576–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astley, W.G. 1984. Toward an Appreciation of Collective Strategy. Academy of Management Review 9: 526–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartunek, J. 1984. Changing Interpretive Schemes and Organizational Restructuring: The Example of a Religious Order. Administrative Science Quarterly 29 (3): 355–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boje, D. 1982. Towards a Theory and Praxis of Transorganizational Development: Stakeholder Networks and Their Habitats. Working paper 79-6. Behavioral and Organizational Science Study Center, Graduate School of Management, Los Angeles: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, S.L., and W.J.D. Kennedy. 1988. Managing Public Disputes: A Practical Guide to Handling Conflict and Reaching Agreements. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E. 1984. Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach. Boston: Pittman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E., and Daniel R. Gilbert. 1989. Corporate Strategy and The Search for Ethics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Business Ethics and Society: A Critical Agenda. Business & Society 31: 9–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter. 1979. The Corporation as a Moral Person. American Philosophical Quarterly 3: 207–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Marilyn. 1989. The Impracticality of Impartiality. Journal of Philosophy LXXVI: 645–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In A Different Voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, Barbara. 1985. Organizations as Constructions and Destructions of Meaning. Journal of Management 11: 83–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Collaborating: Finding Common Ground for Multiparty Problems. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannan, M., and J. Freeman. 1977. The Population Ecology of Organizations. American Journal of Sociology 82: 929–964.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 1986. The Science Question in Feminism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, H. 1985. Shifting Gears. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochan, J., H. Katz, and R. McKersie. 1987. The Transformation of American Industrial Relations. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, C. 1990. Beyond Teamwork. Training 27 (June 1990): 25–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, R.O., and I.I. Mitroff. 1981. Challenging Strategic Planning Assumptions: Theory, Cases and Techniques. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Toole, J. 1987. Vanguard Management: Redesigning the Corporate Future. Garden City: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, T. 1987. Thriving on Chaos: Handbook for a Management Revolution. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, M. 1985. Models of Cooperation and Change in Union Settings. Industrial Relations. 24 (3): 382–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smircich, L. 1983. Organizations as Shared Meaning. In Organizational Symbolism, ed. L.R. Pondy, P. Frost, G. Morgan, and T. Dandridge. Greenwich: JAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, T. 1989. New Ways to Exercise Power. Fortune (November 6) 52-66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Susskind, L.E., and J. Cruikshank. 1987. Breaking the Impasse. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, J. 1976. Resha** the International Order: A Report to the Club of Rome. New York: Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, R. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Bever, D. 1987. HBS Focuses Microscope on General Electric CEO. Harbor News 51 (November 2): 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddock, Sandra. 1986. Public-Private Partnerships as Social Problem Solving: Product and Process. In Research in Corporate Social Performance and Policy, ed. J.E. Post, vol. 8, 273–300. Greenwich: JAI.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Understanding Social Partnerships: An Evolutionary Model of Partnership Organizations. Administration & Society 21: 78–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. A Typology of Social Partnership Organizations. Administration & Society 22: 480–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to R. Edward Freeman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Wicks, A.C., Gilbert, D.R., Freeman, R.E. (2023). A Feminist Reinterpretation of the Stakeholder Concept. In: Dmytriyev, S.D., Freeman, R.E. (eds) R. Edward Freeman’s Selected Works on Stakeholder Theory and Business Ethics. Issues in Business Ethics(), vol 53. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-04564-6_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation