Abstract

This chapter clarifies the essential theoretical background. In opposition to the prevailing diversification of the meaning of the concept of emergence, it advocates universalizing it as a generally valid principle in the creation of complex wholes. Achieving unification and universalization in the creation of new perspectives is one of the primary intentions of science and philosophy; thus, we should not reject it as an option but should seek to establish why it is necessary to limit the search for a universal principle of emergence to ontological emergence and its role in the emergence of complex wholes in different domains of reality. Thus, the starting point is a critical analysis of traditional conceptions of ontological emergence, tracing the fundamental ideas underlying each approach, including the distinction between emergence1 and emergence2 (Searle ), the supervenient (Kim , Van Cleve, O’Connor, McLaughlin, Crane) and non-supervenient conceptions of emergence (Humphreys ), and the influential concept of “weak” and “strong” emergence (Bedau , Chalmers, Gillett).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This list does not attempt to be complete, or to do justice to the specificities of the individual disciplines. On the contrary, although many of these have established a specialised branch of mathematics (e.g. fractal geometry), the processes to which they are applicable are often the subjects of other disciplines. Chaos theory pertains to dynamic systems, which often contain mathematical structures called attractors and fractals.

  2. 2.

    It is correlation if the control system includes feedback, which then correlates the motion of the drone e.g. through its pilot.

  3. 3.

    Compositional laws of the additivity of weight are only valid in Newtonian physics. In relativist physics, relativistic effects must be taken into account; yet it remains a difficult question whether or not these effects should be viewed as emergent.

  4. 4.

    Cf. Mill’s heteropathic and homopathic composition of causes.

  5. 5.

    The best-known realization of a cellular automaton is Conway’s “Game of Life”, demonstrating the formation of various emergent forms, structures and properties based on simple recurrent algorithms. The Game of Life cellular automaton is a 2D grid of cells where cells can have two values. They are full (alive) or empty (dead). A distribution of live and dead cells provides the initial configuration of the grid, following which Conway’s “genetic laws” for birth, death and survival (i.e. rules for changing the values of cells) are applied step by step, allowing one to see the dynamic evolution of changes in the distribution of live and dead cells in the grid. It is remarkable how simple rules lead to the complex behaviour of wholes. “Conway’s genetic laws are delightfully simple. First, each cell of the grid (assumed to be an infinite plane) has eight neighboring cells, four adjacent orthogonally, four adjacent diagonally. The rules are: (1) Survivals. Every live cell with two or three neighboring live cells survives for the next generation. (2) Deaths. Each live cell with four or more live neighbors dies. Every cell with one live neighbor or none dies from isolation. (3) Births. Each empty cell adjacent to exactly three live neighbors—no more, no fewer—is a birth cell at the next move. It is important to understand that all births and deaths occur simultaneously in one step. Together they constitute a single generation in one ‘step’ in the complete ‘life history’ of the initial configuration.” (modified from Gardner 1970)

References

  • Alexander, Samuel. [1920] 1950. Space, Time, and Deity. Macmillan & Co., in two volumes, reprinted 1950 by The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book 8, section 1045a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, David M. 1989. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atmanspacher, Harald. 2002. Determinism Is Ontic, Determinability Is Epistemic. In Between Chance and Choice, ed. Atmanspacher, H. and Bishop, R., Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, Mark A. 1997. Weak Emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 375–399, quoted from Philosophical Perspectives: Mind, Causation, and World, chapter Weak Emergence, 375–399. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Downward Causation and the Autonomy of Weak Emergence. Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 6(1): 5–50. (Reprinted as Downward Causation and the Autonomy in Weak Emergence. In Emergence, ed. Mark A. Bedau and Paul Humphreys, the MIT Press, 2008, 155–188.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Is Weak Emergence Just in the Mind? Minds and Machines 18 (4): 443–459. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-008-9122-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, Mark, and Paul Humphreys, eds. 2008. Emergence: Contemporary Readings in Philosophy and Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, Robert C., and George F.R. Ellis. 2020. Contextual Emergence of Physical Properties. Foundations of Physics 50 (5, May): 481–510. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00333-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, David. 1957. Causality and chance in modern physics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C.D. 1925. The Mind and Its Place in Nature. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, Mario. [2003] 2014. Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge. Toronto Studies in Philosophy. Toronto/Buffalo: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, Philip. 2006. Conceptual Foundations of Emergence Theory. In The Re-Emergence of Emergence, ed. P. Clayton and P. Davies, 1–31. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, Tim. 2000. Dualism, Monism, Physicalism. Mind & Society 1 (2): 73–85. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf02512314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The Significance of Emergence. In Physicalism and Its Discontents, ed. B. Loewer and G. Gillett. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, Bryon. 2001. The Reemergence of ‘Emergence’. Philosophy of Science 3: S63–S75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1970. Mental Events. Reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, ed. D. Davidson. 1980: 207–224. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. 2003. Freedom Evolves. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, Jonardon. 2011. Emergentisms, ancient and modern. Mind 120: 671–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, Carl. 2016. Reduction and Emergence in Science and Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guay, Alexandre, and Olivier Sartenaer. 2016. A New Look at Emergence. Or When after Is Different. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 6 (2): 297–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, Richard Mervyn [1952] 2003. The Language of Morals. Reprinted. Clarendon Paperbacks. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Havlík, Vladimír. 2011. Vstříc univerzálnímu evolučnímu principu. In Z evolučního hlediska, ed. Vladimír Havlík and Tomáš Hříbek et al. Filosofia, Praha.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Searle on Emergence. Organon F 19 (2): 40–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, Paul. 1997a. How Properties Emerge. Philosophy of Science 64: 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997b. Emergence Not Supervenience. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 64, Supplement. Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers, S337-S345.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a. Emergence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. Emergence. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science, Oxford Handbooks, ed. Paul Humphreys, Anjan Chakravartty, Margaret Morrison, and Andrea Woody, 759–778. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, Philippe, and Paul Humphreys. 2008. Dynamical Emergence and Computation: An introduction. Minds and Machines 18 (4): 425–430. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-008-9124-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1978. Supervenience and Nomological Incommensurables. American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (2): 149–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Concepts of Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (2): 153–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept. Metaphilosophy 21, no. 1–2 (1990): 1–27. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.1990.tb00830.x.

  • ———. 1993. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays, Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Making Sense of Emergence. Philosophical Studies 95: 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Supervenience, Emergence, Realization, Reduction. In Loux, Michael J., and Dean W. Zimmerman, ed. The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 556–584.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton University Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400840847.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, Michael. 2014. In Search of Ontological Emergence: Diachronic. But Non-Supervenient. Axiomathes 24 (1): 89–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klee, Robert L. 1984. Micro-Determinism and Concepts of Emergence. Philosophy of Science 51 (1): 44–63. https://doi.org/10.1086/289163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes, George Henry. [1875] 2009. Problems of Life and Mind. the @study of Psychology: Its Object, Scope, and Method Third Series, Third Series, Whitefish (Mont.): Kessinger publishing, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David K. [1986] 2001. On the Plurality of Worlds. Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limmer, David T., and David Chandler. 2013. The Putative Liquid-Liquid Transition Is a Liquid-Solid Transition in Atomistic Models of Water II. The Journal of Chemical Physics 138 (21): 214504. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.4807479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, Brian P. [1995] 2007. Varieties of Supervenience. In Supervenience: New Essays, ed. E. Savellos and Ü. Yalçin, 16–59. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997a. Emergence and supervenience. Intellectica 25: 25–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997b. Supervenience, Vagueness, and Determination. Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 11, Mind, Causation, and World, 209–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, Brian P., and Karen Bennett. 2005. Supervenience. Stanford Encyklopedia of Philosophy, First published Mon Jul 25: 2005. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/. Accessed 4 July 2021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John S. [1843] 2011. A System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive, Being a connected view of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation, eBooks@Adelaide.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, George Edward. 1922. Philosophical Studies. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. Lloyd. 1923. Emergent Evolution. London: Williams & Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Timothy. 1994. Emergent Properties. American Philosophical Quarterly 31: 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Timothy, and Hong Yu Wong. 2005. The Metaphysics of Emergence. Noûs 39 (4): 658–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perakis, Fivos et al. 2017. Diffusive dynamics during the high-to-low density transition in amorphous ice. PNAS, vol. 114(31): s. 8193–8198. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1705303114.

  • Poole, Peter H., Francesco Sciortino, Ulrich Essmann, and H. Eugene Stanley. 1992. Phase Behaviour of Metastable Water. Nature 360 (6402): 324–328. https://doi.org/10.1038/360324a0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Primas, Hans. 1998. Emergence in Exact Natural Science. Acta Polytechnica Scandinavica Mathematics and Computing Series 91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigato, Joana. 2017. Looking for Emergence in Physics. Phenomenology and Mind 2017: 174–183. https://doi.org/10.13128/PHE_MI-21116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ronald, E., M. Sipper, and M. Capcarrère. 1999. Design, observation, surprise! A test of emergence. Artificial Life 5 (3): 225–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, Alex. 1997. Can Physicalist Antireductionism Compute the Embryo? Philosophy of Science, Vol. 64, Supplement. Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meetingsof the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers. S359–S371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savellos, Elias E, and Ümit D. Yalçin . [1995] 2014. Supervenience: New Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaruffi, Piero. 1999. John Searle: The Rediscovery of the Mind. https://www.scaruffi.com/mind/searle.html. Accessed 3 June 2021.

  • Schlick, Moritz. 1979. The Future of Philosophy. In Philosophical Papers, ed. H.L. Mulder and B.F.B. van de Velde-Schlick, vol. 2, 210–224. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge, the MIT Press, kapitola 5, Reductionism and the Irreducibility of Consciousness. Cite from: Emergence, ed. M. A. Bedau, P. Humphreys, the MIT Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Reply to Commentators. In Organon F, Philosophy of John Searle, vol. 19, Supplementary Issue 2, 199–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheibe, Erhard. 1973. The Logical Analysis of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, Michael, and John McGeever. 1999. The Search for Ontological Emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly 49 (195): 201–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, Michael, (Ed.). 1999. Laws of Nature, Causation, and Supervenience. Analytical Metaphysics 1. New York: Garland Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. 1990. Mind-Dust or Magic? Panpsychism versus Emergence. Philosophical Perspectives: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind 4: 215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William C. 1997. Aggregativity: Reductive Heuristics for Finding Emergence. Philosophy of Science 64 (4): 372–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Havlík, V. (2022). Towards a Universal Principle of Emergence (UPE). In: Hierarchical Emergent Ontology and the Universal Principle of Emergence. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-98148-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation