Reductive Neurophilosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy and Neuroscience

Part of the book series: New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science ((NDPCS))

  • 371 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter investigates the approach that can be considered directly opposed to the main ideas of the isolationist approach, arguing that, contrariwise, neuroscience has a lot to contribute to philosophy, as long as the second is updated to a method that can incorporates empirical knowledge. The “Reductive Approach” (RA) seeks, first of all, to be an “application of neuroscientific discoveries to traditional questions of Philosophy” (Bickle, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. Oxford University Press, 2009, p. 4). The aim is to reformulate the philosophical work that has been considered, until then, as a work of conceptual analysis based on a priori methodologies, by a methodology that incorporates the data of science and can use them to solve the traditional problems of the philosophy of mind. However, (RA) is much more radical than this quote: at its basis is the fundamental thesis that philosophical concepts should tend to be replaced by neuroscientific concepts. We will analyse in detail the basic principles and the metaphilosophical assumptions of this approach. To this end, we will analyse two proponents, in different versions, of (RA): Patricia Churchland and John Bickle.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 93.08
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 117.69
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 117.69
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Original quote: “Ein Gegenstand (oder Begriff) heißt auf einen oder mehrere andere Gegenstände ‘zurückführbar’, wenn alle Aussage über ihn sich umformen lassen in Aussagen über diese anderen Gegenstände” (Carnap, 1928, p. 1).

  2. 2.

    McCloskey (1983) investigated empirically that many people with less knowledge or information believe in a physical theory of intuition and are, therefore, more Aristotelian than Newtonians in relation to movement.

  3. 3.

    Some authors call the validity of this argument into question, since they argue that we can defend the existence of propositional attitudes without having to defend Folk Psychology (cf. Kitcher, 1984; Von Eckardt, 1994).

  4. 4.

    We can, of course, answer that stagnation is a sign that it is correct and effective and that, precisely for that reason, it does not need to be changed. Or, like Hacker, that there is no progress because only (real) theories can make progress and (FP) is not a theory, as we will see in the criticisms.

  5. 5.

    This can be seen as false: a lot of contemporary research—in Psychology, History, Moral Theory, Criminology and so on—uses (FP) in its view of the world and it has been useful in scientific research itself, as argued by Horgan and Woodward (1985) or Greenwood (1991).

  6. 6.

    A defence of a specific kind of introspection will be presented in the next chapter (Neurophenomenological Approach).

  7. 7.

    Some authors reject that Bickle was successful. For example, João Fonseca states that “[Bickle] is unable to] provide an effective procedure that locates an arbitrary reduction in the spectrum in an absolute way. This location can only be established in a parochial and internal way and not in an absolute and external way” (Fonseca, 2006, pp. 129–130).

  8. 8.

    Specifically, the Reductionist Approach will make use of a “replacement naturalism”, as we will see in Chap. 5.

  9. 9.

    This passage is derived from the German original: “Und trotzdem gibt es Philosophen, welche sich weigern, die wissenschaftliche Philosophie als Philosophie anzuerkennen und sie lieber in das Einleitungskapitel eines wissenschaftlichen Lehrbuchs verweisen möchten; Philosophen, welche immer noch behaupten, daß es eine unabhängige Philosophie gibt, die nichts mit wissenschaftlicher Forschung zu tun hat, sondern ihren eigenen Zugang zur Wahrheit besitzt. Solche Ansprüche offenbaren meiner Ansicht nach das Fehlen jeder Kritik. Diejenigen, welche die Fehler der traditionellen Philosophie nicht erkennen, wollen natürlich ihre Ergebnisse und Methoden nicht aufgeben und ziehen es vor, auf einem Pfad weiterzugehen, den die wissenschaftliche Philosophie längst verlassen hat. Sie reservieren den Namen Philosophie für ihre mit Fehlschlüssen durchsetzten Versuche, eine überwissenschaftliche Erkenntnis aufzufinden, und weigern sich, eine Methode als philosophisch zu bezeichnen, die sich die wissenschaftliche Forschung zum Muster angenommen hat. Wer einer wissenschaftlichen Philosophie gerecht werden will, muß seine philosophischen Wünsche und Ziele revidieren” (Reichenbach, 1968, p. 305).

References

  • Balzer, W., Moulines, C., & Sneed, J. (1987). An Architectonic for Science. D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2006). Reducing Mind to Molecular Pathways: Explicating the Reductionism Implicit in Current Cellular and Molecular Neuroscience. Synthese, 151, 411–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (Ed.). (2009). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy (R. George, Trad.). University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1934). The Unity of Science (M. Black, Trad.). Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1985). Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 8–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1988). Matter and Consciousness. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson. In Y. Nagasawa, P. Ludlow, & D. Stoljar (Eds.), A Neurocomputational Perspective (pp. 163–178). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1994). Folk Psychology. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (pp. 308–316). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1996). Do We Propose to Eliminate Consciousness? In R. McCauley (Ed.), The Churchlands and Their Critics (pp. 297–301). Blackwell..

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç, B. (1983). In Defense of the Identity Theory. The Journal of Philosophy, 80(5), 279–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1962). Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time—Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Vol. 3, pp. 28–97). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special Sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis. Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1981). Representations. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fonseca, J. (2006). Uma abordagem anti-realista contra a formulação do problema mente-corpo segundo uma perspectiva reducionista-interteórica. In S. Miguens, J. Pinto, & C. Mauro (Eds.), Análises: Actas do 2° Encontro Nacional de Filosofia Analítica (pp. 124–133). Faculdade de Letras da Universidade do Porto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1988). Explaining Science. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1992). In Defense of the Simulation Theory. Mind and Language, 7, 104–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. (1992). Why the Child’s Theory of Mind Really is a Theory. Mind and Language, 7, 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. (1986). Folk Psychology as Simulation. Mind and Language, 1, 158–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. (1992). Replies to Stich and Nichols and Perner and Howes. Mind and Language, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, J. (1991). The Future of Folk Psychology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. (1981). Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part I: Historical and Scientific Setting. Part II: Identity in Reduction. Part III: Cross-Categorical Reduction. Dialogue, 20, 38–59, 201–236, 496–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Woodward, J. (1985). Folk Psychology is Here to Stay. Philosophical Review, 94, 197–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kandel, E., & Hawkins, R. (1984). Is There a Cell-Biological Alphabet for Simple Forms of Learning? Psychological Review, 91, 375–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a Physical World. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). In Defense of Intentional Psychology. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 89–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Collier, J., & Spurrett, D. (2007). Everything Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Art, Mind, and Religion. Journal of Philosophy, 66(1), 22–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loemker, L. (Ed. & Trans.). (1969). G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters (2nd ed.). D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, M. (1983). Intuitive Physics. Scientific American, 248(4), 122–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mormann, T. (1991). Husserl’s Philosophy of Science and the Semantic Approach. Philosophy of Science, 58(1), 61–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. Harcourt, Brace, and World.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1983). Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes. The Psychological Review, 84(3), 231–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G. (2014). Minding the Brain: A Guide to Philosophy & Neuroscience. Red Globe Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Kemeny, J. (1956). On Reduction. Philosophical Studies, 7, 6–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S., Gilbert, P., & Burwood, S. (2013). An Introduction to Metaphilosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The Nature of Mental States. In Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Vol. II. Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1969). Epistemology Naturalized. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (pp. 69–90). Columbia University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1981). Theories and Things. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1995). From Stimulus to Science. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2006). ‘Folk Psychology’ is Not Folk Psychology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1968). Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie. Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R., & Wagner, A. (1972). A Theory of Pavlovian Conditioning: Variations in the Effectiveness of Reinforcement and Nonreinforcement. In A. Black & W. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical Conditioning. II: Current Research and Theory (pp. 12–33). Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1967). Approaches to Reduction. Philosophy of Science, 34, 137–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. In H. Feigl & M. Striven (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 253–329). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer, J. (1968). Philosophy of Mind. Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. (1967). Types of Inter-theoretic Reduction. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 18, 109–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J. (1971). The Logical Structure of Mathematical Physics. D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., & Nichols, S. (2003). Folk Psychology. In S. Stich & T. Warfield (Eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind (pp. 235–255). Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., & Ravenscroft, I. (1992). What is Folk Psychology? Cognition, 50, 447–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1974). The Structure of Scientific Theories. University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1956). Introduction to Logic. Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1972). A Formal Approach to the Philosophy of Science. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Paradigms and Paradoxes (pp. 303–351). University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Eckardt, B. (1994). Folk Psychology. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Mind (pp. 317–319). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R. (1989). The Coherence Theory of Truth: Realism, Anti-realism, Idealism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, W. (1958). The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (1992). Variable Reduction Not Proven. Philosophical Quarterly, 42, 214–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gouveia, S.S. (2022). Reductive Neurophilosophy. In: Philosophy and Neuroscience. New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-95369-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation