Synthesis and Similarity in Science: Analogy in the Application of Mathematics and Application of Mathematics to Analogy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metaphors and Analogies in Sciences and Humanities

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 453))

  • 578 Accesses

Abstract

Examining different cases, I show that, and how, analogies play a variety of roles in the application of mathematics. Different purposes may involve different cognitive and methodological tasks, some more descriptive – clustering –, others more heuristic – problem-solving and guiding metaphors – and others more evidentiary – robustness analysis and statistical inference in single studies and meta-analyses. Classification, generalization and justification cannot be easily reduced to basic standard patterns of analogical reasoning. I discuss two, however, main kinds of cases: the roles of analogy in the application of mathematics and, connectedly, the role of mathematics in the representation and implementation of analogical cognition.

Moreover, while the relevant similarities get a mathematical expression, the case of machine learning, including the case of similarity metrics and cluster analysis, shows that analogical cognition is not ultimately mathematical. And what I call the analogical circle is virtuous. But I also point to mathematical metaphors and, in relation to mathematical representations of similarity in clustering analysis, raise the issue of the possibility of mathematical representation of metaphoric function itself.

The different cases show in a new way also that the dependence on subjective judgment, research purpose, data characteristics and background information render the application of mathematics and analogical cognition, when connected, unavoidably contextual and plural.

The cases I have presented show also how analogy-driven or aided applications of mathematics connect analogical and synthetic tasks, and that they do so in different ways. They show, more specifically, also that each kind of task is a two-sided coin, so to speak, in scientific cognition and methodology. Synthesis involves also some form of differentiation or analysis, and connectedly, similarity is inseparable from dissimilarity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 117.69
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 149.79
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 149.79
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am grateful to Dedre Gentner for providing the source.

  2. 2.

    Maxwell’s methodological thinking about analogies borrowed from his interests in language and reasoning. He was educated and self-educated in the Aristotelian tradition of logic and rhetoric and in the new formulations of inductive scientific methodology of Herschel, Mill and Whewell. He was also an avid reader of romantic literature and poem writer and a prolific illustrator and draftsman of geometrical and ornamental designs (Cat, 2013). He viewed the application of mathematics accordingly, as a practice of exact but vivid language in the general representation of physical phenomena.

  3. 3.

    Maxwell was explicit about the role of formal analogies. Thus, Maxwell claimed (1) that the correctness of physical analogies depends on the mathematical analogy, namely, that related quantities belong in the same mathematical classes (Maxwell, 1856, 157, 1870, 219), and (2) that mathematical classes are in turn based on mathematical analogies (Maxwell, 1870, 227). Those mathematical analogies are entertained in the mind, however, as far from purely symbolic and formal.

  4. 4.

    Maxwell’s analogies between mechanics and electricity or magnetism differed in this sense from William Thomson’s. As Nersessian puts it: ‘Maxwell did not make direct analogies between the domains. Rather, he constructed intermediary, hybrid models that embodied constraints from Newtonian sources and the electromagnetic target domain. Abstractive processes, especially generic modeling, enabled integrating selective constraints from the different domains because they were considered at a level of generality that eliminated the domain-specific differences.’ (Nersessian, 2018, 60)

References

  • Alpaydin, E. (2004). Introduction to machine learning. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. (2010). By parallel reasoning: The construction and evaluation of analogical arguments. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. (2019). Analogy and analogical reasoning. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-analogy/

  • Biela, A. (1991). Analogy in science. Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boge, F. J. (2020). How to infer explanations from computer simulations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 82, 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bophal, R. S. (2002). Concepts of epidemiology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camastra, F., & Vinciarelli, A. (2008). Machine learning for audio, image and video analysis. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2001). On understanding: Maxwell on the methods of illustration and scientific metaphor. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 33B(3), 395–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2005). Modelling cracks and cracking models: Structures, mechanisms, boundary conditions, constraints, inconsistencies and the proper domains of natural laws. Synthese, 146(3), 441–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2013). Maxwell, Sutton the birth of color photography: A binocular study. Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2015). An informal meditation on empiricism and approximation in fuzzy logic and fuzzy set theory: Between subjectivity and normativity. In R. Seising, E. Trillas, & J. Kacprzyk (Eds.), Towards the future of fuzzy logic (pp. 179–234). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2017). The unity of science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-unity/

  • Cooper, H, Hedges, L. V. (2009). Research synthesis as a scientific process. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 3–16).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, H., Hedges, L. V., & Valentine, J. C. (Eds.). (2009). The handbook of research synthesis and meta-analysis (2nd ed.). Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dardashti, R., Thébault, K. P., & Winsberg, E. (2017). Conformation via analogue simulation: What dumb holes could tell us about gravity. British Journal of Philosophical Science, 68(1), 55–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dufour, C. (2012). Robustness of an experimental result: The example of the tests of Bell’s inequalities. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 147–168).

    Google Scholar 

  • Everitt, B. S., Landau, S., Leese, M., & Stahl, D. (Eds.). (2011). Cluster analysis (5th ed.). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A. A. (2018). Inductive reasoning in the context of discovery: Analogy as an experimental stratagem in the history and philosophy of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A, 69, 23–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D. (1983). Structure-map**: A theoretical framework for analogy. Cognitive Science, 7, 155–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., & Smith, L. A. (2013). Analogical learning and reasoning. In D. Reisberg (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of cognitive psychology (pp. 668–681). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., Holyoak, K., & Kokinov, B. (Eds.). (2001). The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gower, J. C., & Legendre, P. (1986). Metric and Euclidean properties of dissimilarity coefficients. Journal of Classification, 5, 5–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1986). Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallyn, F. (Ed.). (2000). Metaphor and analogy in the sciences. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helman, D. H. (Ed.). (1988). Analogical reasoning: perspectives of artificial intelligence, cognitive science, and philosophy. Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1966). Models and analogies in science. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. (1995). Fluid concepts and creative analogies. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D., & Sander, E. (2013). Surfaces and essences: Analogy as the fuel and fire of thinking. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holman, B. (2019). In defense of meta-analysis. Synthese, 196(8), 3189–3211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K., & Thagard, P. (1989). Analogical map** by constraint satisfaction. Cognitive Science, 13, 295–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hon, G., & Goldstein, B. (2008). From summetria to symmetry: The making of a revolutionary scientific concept. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, A., & Wiliams, M. (2012). Aggregative evidence about the positive and negative effects of treatments. Artificial Intelligence in Medicine, 56, 173–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kline, S. J. (1986). Similitude and approximation theory. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klir, G.J and B. Yuan (1995).Fuzzy Sets and fuzzy logic. Theory and applications. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krömer, R. (2012). Are we still Babylonians? The structure of the foundation of mathematics from a Wimsattian perspective. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 189–206).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leatherdale, W. H. (1974). The role of analogy, model and metaphor in science. North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehtinen, A. (2013). On the impossibility of amalgamating evidence. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 44(1), 101–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsey, M. W. (2009). Identifying interesting variables and analysis opportunities. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 147–158).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1966). Polarity and analogy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M., & McCoy, C. D. (Eds.). (2020). Understanding perspectivism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. C. (1856). On Faraday’s lines of force. In J. C. Maxwell (Ed.) 1890 (Vol. 1, pp. 155–229).

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. C. (1870). Address to the mathematical and physical sections of the British Association. In J. C. Maxwell (Ed.) 1890 (Vol. 2, pp. 215–229).

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. C. (1890). Scientific papers of James Clerk Maxwell (2 vols.). In W. D. Niven (Ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michie, D., Spiegelhalter, D. J., & Taylor, C. C. (1994). Machine learning, neural and statistical classification. Ellis Horwood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nederbragt, H. (2012). Multiple derivability and the reliability and stabilization of theories. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 121–146).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (1984). Faraday to Einstein: Constructing meaning in scientific theories. Martinus Nijhoff/Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2018). Creating scientific concepts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2010). There are no universal rules for induction. Philosophy of Science, 77, 765–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ortony, A. (Ed.). (1979). Metaphor and thought. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwin, R. G., & Vevea, J. L. (2009). Evaluating coding decisions. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 177–203).

    Google Scholar 

  • Polya, G. (1954). Mathematics and plausible reasoning (2 vols.). Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedov, L. I. (1960). Dimensional and similarity methods in mechanics. Academic Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shadish, W. R., & Haddock, C. K. (2009). Combining estimates of effect size. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 257–277).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (2003). Multiples analogies in science and philosophy. North Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2011). Does temperature have a metric structure? Philosophy of Science, 78(3), 472–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soler, L. (2012). The solidity of scientific achievements: Structure of the problem, difficulties, philosophical implications. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 1–60).

    Google Scholar 

  • Soler, L., Trizio, E., Nickles, T., & Wimsatt, W. C. (Eds.). (2012). Characterizing robustness in science. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga, J. (2009). Robustness, discordance, and relevance. Philosophy of Science, 76, 650–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga, J. (2011). Is meta-analysis the platinum standard of evidence? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42(4), 497–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga, J. (2012). Rerum Concordia Discord: Robustness and discordant multimodal evidence. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 207–226).

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Valentine, J. C. (2009). Judging the quality of primary research. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 129–146).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wieber, F. (2012). Multiple means of determination and multiple constraints of construction: Robustness and strategies for modeling macromolecular objects. In L. Soler et al. (Eds.) (pp. 267–288).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. B. (2009). Systematic coding. In H. Cooper et al. (Eds.) (pp. 159–176).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, J. E. (2020). Representationalism in measurement theory. Structuralism or perspectivalism? In M. Massimi & C. D. McCoy (Eds.) (pp. 109–126).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jordi Cat .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cat, J. (2022). Synthesis and Similarity in Science: Analogy in the Application of Mathematics and Application of Mathematics to Analogy. In: Wuppuluri, S., Grayling, A.C. (eds) Metaphors and Analogies in Sciences and Humanities. Synthese Library, vol 453. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-90688-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation