• 236 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter first develops a Foucauldian theory of power, then applies it to analyze the apparatus that controls the operation of the truth predicate within the social fabric—what Foucault calls the regime of truth. Throughout, I focus on how the operation of power on the functioning of the word “true” within a social fabric beset with inequity and oppression is distinct from truth itself. Whether a sentence is true or false is not decided by the operation of power. Truth itself is not the product of power. But our social epistemic fabric is strongly influenced by power, to the point where political struggle for control over the social epistemic apparatus that controls the operation of the truth predicate cannot be disentangled from our epistemic struggle to generate knowledge of the truth, especially where the truth concerns systems of oppression.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Spain)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 53.49
Price includes VAT (Spain)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 67.59
Price includes VAT (Spain)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 93.59
Price includes VAT (Spain)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For example, the methods of mainstream analytic philosophy may be taken for granted, simply assumed, while a critical theory paper presented in an analytic context must justify and defend its methodology—against extreme skepticism—in addition to making its central point.

  2. 2.

    Foucault (1972/1980), Foucault (1978/1990).

  3. 3.

    Foucault (1978), p. 92, including the following quotes to be explained.

  4. 4.

    Ibid., p. 92.

  5. 5.

    Even the most powerfully predictive social dynamic theory ever imagined—psychohistory—falls prey to this essential shortcoming; see Isaac Asimov’s (2004) Foundation and Empire.

  6. 6.

    Ibid., p. 92. The proceeding quotations are all from this passage.

  7. 7.

    This part makes me think of Hobbes’s (1651) Leviathan. The sovereign or the state can be decomposed when the social order fails, in which case what remains is the power of the individuals in the state of nature. The microscopic constituents of macroscopic social entities like the sovereign or the state include the myriad power relations that exist in the state of nature among people, including their physical abilities, their weapons, and their knowledge. When these micro power relations are organized in a certain way through the social contract, the sovereign is created and imbued with power from below. Of course, Foucault’s theory of power is much more generalized than social contract theory.

  8. 8.

    This idea is an artifact of De Saussure’s (1916) linguistic theory, semiotics, which postulates that semantics depends on binary opposition: words only have semantic values insofar as their semantic function can be contrasted with an oppositional term. Binary opposition is also the precondition for deconstruction as that concept was deployed by Derrida (1967). Binary opposition is not entailed by model-theoretic semantics, which can assign meanings to terms which have no binary oppositional term. For example, the expression “trumpet” can be assigned an extension, the set of trumpets, without postulating that there is some term which is the binary opposite of “trumpet” (which I suppose would be a word for all and only non-trumpets?). Most analytic philosophers of language reject binary opposition as a precondition on semantic value. This fact has something to do with why analytic philosophers are typically baffled by Derrida’s concept of deconstruction.

  9. 9.

    Steinbeck (1939), Chap. 5.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., p. 94.

  11. 11.

    Ibid., p. 93.

  12. 12.

    Ibid., p. 93.

  13. 13.

    Foucault et al. (1980), p. 132.

  14. 14.

    Ibid., p. 132.

  15. 15.

    Ibid., p. 131.

  16. 16.

    Foucault (1978), pp. 101–102.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., p. 131.

  18. 18.

    Trump (2020).

  19. 19.

    Ibid.

  20. 20.

    See Code (2012), Harding (1995), and Scheman (1995).

  21. 21.

    Ibid., p. 133.

  22. 22.

    The syntactical conception I am presenting is very much influenced by Neurath’s (1983) conception of the operation of statements within a social fabric (see also Anderson, 2019). As far as I know, it is an unexplored question whether Foucault ever read Neurath’s work. It would not be completely surprising given that Neurath was a Marxist philosopher of science with an interest in the role of truth in politics.

  23. 23.

    Foucault (1980), “Truth and Power,” pp. 131–132. Bracketed numbers added.

References

  • Alexander, M. (2020). The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness. The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, D. (2019). Rejecting Semantic Truth: On the Significance of Neurath’s Syntacticism. In Neurath Reconsidered (pp. 363–382). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1967). Truth and Politics. Truth: Engagements Across Philosophical Traditions, 295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asimov, I. (2004). Foundation and Empire (Vol. 2). Spectra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1985). A Rationale for Reliabilism. The Monist, 68, 246–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1977). Theory of Knowledge (2nd ed.). Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (2012). Taking Subjectivity into Account. In Education, Culture and Epistemological Diversity (pp. 85–100). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S., & Lehrer, K. (1983). Justification, Truth, and Knowledge. Synthese, 55, 191–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P. H. (2002). Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Saussure, F. (1916/2011). Course in General Linguistics. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1989). The Intentional Stance. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1967/2016). Of Grammatology. Jhu Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing. Hypatia, 26(2), 236–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1997). Special Sciences: Still Autonomous After All These Years. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 149–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special Sciences (Or: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis). Synthese, 97–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1975/2012). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1978/1990). The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M., Rabinow, P., & Martell, L. (1972). Truth and Power. In Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977. Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1993). When Logic Meets Politics: Testimony, Distrust, and Rhetorical Disadvantage. Informal Logic, 15(2). https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v15i2.2476

  • Harding, S. (1995). “Strong objectivity”: A Response to the New Objectivity Question. Synthese, 104(3), 331–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651/1980). Leviathan. Glasgow 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. (2007). White Ignorance. Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, 247, 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, M. (1983). Philosophical Papers 1913–1946: With a Bibliography of Neurath in English (Vol. 16). Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oxford English Dictionary. (2020a). “female, n.” OED Online. Oxford University Press, December 2020. Oed.com.

  • Oxford English Dictionary. (2020b). “woman, n.” OED Online. Oxford University Press, December 2020. Oed.com.

  • Scheman, N. (1995). Feminist Epistemology. Metaphilosophy, 26(3), 177–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinbeck, J. (1939/2006). The Grapes of Wrath. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trump, D. (2020). Remarks by President Trump at the White House Conference on American History, September 17, 2020. https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/remarks-president-trump-white-house-conference-american-history/ [Removed by Biden Administration].

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Derek Egan Anderson .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Anderson, D.E. (2021). Power and Regimes of Truth. In: Metasemantics and Intersectionality in the Misinformation Age. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73339-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation