Abductive Inference, Self-Knowledge, and the Myth of Introspection

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Abduction in Cognition and Action

Abstract

Much of the history of psychology can be understood as a debate over what we do when we attribute psychological states to ourselves and to others. In the classic Cartesian view, those activities are quite distinct: We engage an infallible ability—introspection—when examining our own psychological states, but merely speculate when trying to identify the psychological states of others. The American Philosopher, Charles Sanders Peirce dedicated several early papers to a critique of the Cartesian approach. He concluded that attempts at self-knowledge require the same inferential processes that we use when attributing mental states to others, and therefore incur the same logical risks. By pursing these ideas further, we intend to show that self-knowledge results from a special kind of abduction; the inference of behavior states from particular observed behaviors. Such inferences allow us to anticipate yet-unseen patterns of behavior in yet-to-be-manifested circumstances.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 96.29
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See [1], and several chapters in this volume.

  2. 2.

    American Philosophy scholars might well point out that we are slightly muddling how Peirce might be expected to present these ideas with how James might be expected to present them. As we are psychologists, building towards insights about the field of psychology, we will own any such criticisms for the time being.

  3. 3.

    Peirce deplored any casuistic understanding of Pragmatism so much that he eventually felt the need to distinguish his approach by adding an extra syllable and calling it Pragmaticism. In the same spirit, N.S.T believes we could bring clarity by editing The Maxim to add a syllable to the word “practicial.” That would stress the fact that Peirce was using “pragmatic” in the sense of a practice, especially adherence to longstanding scientific practices of laboratory science, inter-laboratory debate and cooperation, and theoretical analysis. The Pragmaticist Maxim would then read, “Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practicial bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.”

References

  1. Campos, D.G.: On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s Inference to the best explanation. Synthese 180, 419–442 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Charles, E.P.: ToM 101: a guide to mainstream theory of mind research [Review of the book Theory of mind: How children understand others’ thoughts and feelings, by M. J. Doherty]. PsycCRITIQUES 54(15) (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Charles, E.P.: Myths and missteps in “theory of mind” dogma [Review of the book Against theory of mind, by I. Leudar & A. Costall, Eds.]. PsycCRITIQUES 55(25) (2010). https://doi.org/10.1037/a0020186

  4. Charles, E.P.: Seeing minds in behavior: descriptive mentalism. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 15(3), 267–276 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Charles, E.P., Bybee, M.D., Thompson, N.S.: A behaviorist account of emotions and feelings: making sense of James D. Laird’s Feelings: The perception of self. Behav. Philos. 39, 1–16 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Charles, E., Dege, M.: The beyond must also be useful: the burden of alternative approaches. Integr. Psychol. Behav. Sci. 42(2), 194–199 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Charles, E.P., Golonka, S., Wilson, A.D.: The most important thing neuropragmatism can do: providing an alternative to ‘cognitive’ neuroscience. In: Shook, J.R., Solymosi, T. (eds.) Pragmatist Neurophilosophy: American Philosophy and the Brain, pp. 127–149 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  8. de Waal, C. (ed.): American New Realism 1910–1920. Thoemmes Press, Bristol, United Kingdom (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Doherty, M.J.: Theory of Mind: How Children Understand Others’ Thoughts and Feelings. Psychology Press, New York (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Houser, N.: Peirce’s Post-Jamesian Pragmatism. Eur. J. Pragmatism Am. Philos. [Online], III-1 (2011). URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/866

  11. Heft, H.: Ecological Psychology in Context: James Gibson, Roger Barker, and the Legacy of William James’ Radical Empiricism. Erlbaum Inc, Mahwah, NJ (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Laird, J.D.: Feelings: The Perception of Self. Oxford University Press, New York (2007)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Leudar, I., Costal, A.: Against Theory of Mind. Palgrave Macmillan, New York (2009)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Miller, S.A.: Theory of Mind: Beyond the Preschool Years. Psychology Press, New York (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Peirce, C.S.: Questions concerning certain faculties claimed for man. J. Speculative Philos. 2, 103–114 (1868)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Peirce, C.S.: Some consequences of four incapacities. J. Speculative Philos. 2, 140–157 (1868)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Peirce, C.S.: Grounds of validity of the laws of logic: further consequences of four incapacities. J. Speculative Philos. 2, 193–208 (1869)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Peirce, C.S.: The fixation of belief. Popular Sci. Monthly 12, 1–15 (1877)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Peirce, C.S.: How to make our ideas clear. Popular Sci. Monthly 12, 286–302 (1878)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Smith, L.D.: Behaviorism and Logical Positivism: A Reassessment of the Alliance. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Thompson, N.S.: The many perils of ejective anthropomorphism. Behav. Philos. 22, 59–70 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Thompson, N.S.: Communication and natural design. In: Thompson, N.S. (series ed.), Owings, D., Beecher, M. (vol. eds.) Perspectives in Ethology, vol. 12: Communication. Plenum, New York (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Thompson, N.S.: Signs and designs. Behav. Philos. 46, 25–46 (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Thompson, N.S., Charles, E.P.: Interview with an old new realist. In: Charles, E.P. (ed.) A New Look at New Realism: The Psychology and Philosophy of E. B. Holt, pp. xxxi–lviii. Transaction Publishers, Piscataway, NJ (2011)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Phillip Charles .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Charles, E.P., Thompson, N.S. (2021). Abductive Inference, Self-Knowledge, and the Myth of Introspection. In: Shook, J.R., Paavola, S. (eds) Abduction in Cognition and Action. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 59. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-61773-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation