A Panenmentalist Reconsideration of the Identity of Indiscernibles

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Panenmentalist Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 424))

  • 155 Accesses

Abstract

If we consider any two entities (such as the two spheres in Max Black’s well-known thought-experiment) as individual possibilities, pure or actual, they cannot be considered indiscernible at all. Since allegedly indiscernible possibilities are necessarily one and the same possibility, any numerically distinct (at least two) possibilities must be discernible, independently of their properties, “monadic” or relational. Hence, any distinct possibility is also discernible. Metaphysically-ontologically, the identity of indiscernibles as possibilities is thus necessary, even though epistemic discernibility is still lacking or does not exist. Because any actuality is of an individual pure possibility, the identity also holds for actual indiscernibles. The metaphysical or ontological necessity of the identity of indiscernibles renders, I believe, any opposition to it entirely groundless.

A first version of this chapter was published in Metaphysica 6:2 (October 2005), pp. 25–51.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Leibniz, Russell, Whitehead, F. H. Bradley, and McTaggart supported it, whereas Wittgenstein (the locus classicus is Tractatus 5.5302, criticizing Russell and arguing that two distinct objects may have all their properties in common), C. S. Peirce, G. E. Moore, C. D. Broad, and Max Black are among its strong opponents. The support may adopt an idealistic stance, while the opposition is clearly anti-idealistic or empiricist.

  2. 2.

    Black’s arguments have been discussed by Hacking (1975), Adams (1979), Casullo (1982), Denkel (1991), Landini and Foster (1991), French (1995), Cross (1995), O’Leary-Hawthorne (1995), Vallicella (1997), Zimmerman (1998), and Rodriguez-Pereyra (2004). Nevertheless, there is still room enough for alternative treatments of it on quite different grounds (especially different from those of fictionalism, the bundle theory, or haecceitism).

  3. 3.

    Individual pure possibilities are exempt from any spatiotemporality. Can a sphere as a pure possibility be exempt from space? Yes, it can. Think of any figure, such as sphere, in the analytical geometry, which transforms any spatial distinction to algebraic properties. Although in Kantian terms, even algebraic properties are subject to temporality, since the arithmetic series is subject to it, yet my view is by no means Kantian, especially concerning spatiotemporality and the identity of indiscernibles. As a result, as individual pure possibilities, the two spheres are entirely exempt from spatiotemporality.

  4. 4.

    For some other instructive examples of blind arguments versus illuminating insights see Gilead 2004a.

  5. 5.

    Consult Adams (1979, pp. 13–17), following Black (1952, p. 161) and Hacking (1975). Cf., however, Denkel (1991, pp. 214–15, footnote 3), Landini and Foster (1991, pp. 55–60), and French (1995, pp. 461–466).

  6. 6.

    As quoted in Black (1952, p. 163); cf. Casullo (1982, p. 595–596), Landini and Foster (1991, pp. 54–55, 58–60).

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1979). Primitive thisness and primitive identity. The Journal of Philosophy, 76, 5–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1952). The identity of Indiscernibles. Mind, 61, 153–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casullo, A. (1982). Particulars, substrata, and the identity of Indiscernibles. Philosophy of Science, 49, 591–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cross, C. B. (1995). Max Black on the identity of Indiscernibles. The Philosophical Quarterly, 45, 350–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denkel, A. (1991). Principia Individuationis. The Philosophical Quarterly, 41, 212–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (1995). Hacking away at the identity of Indiscernibles: Possible worlds and Einstein’s principle of equivalence. The Journal of Philosophy, 92, 455–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilead, A. (1999). Saving possibilities: An essay in philosophical psychology (Value Inquiry Book Series) (Vol. 80). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilead, A. (2003). Singularity and Other Possibilities: Panenmentalist Novelties (Value Inquiry Book Series) (Vol. 139). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilead, A. (2004a). Philosophical blindness: Between arguments and insights. The Review of Metaphysics, 58, 147–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilead, A. (2004b). How many pure possibilities are there? Metaphysica, 5, 85–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1975). The identity of indiscernibles. The Journal of Philosophy, 72, 249–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landini, G., & Foster, R. T. (1991). The persistence of counterexample: Re-examining the debate over Leibniz Law. Noûs, 25, 43–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1995). The bundle theory of substance and the identity of Indiscernibles. Analysis, 55, 191–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1999). How many possible worlds are there? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59, 403–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2003). Nonexistents then and now. The Review of Metaphysics, 57, 359–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallicella, W. F. (1997). Bundles and indiscernibility: A reply to O’Leary-Hawthorne. Analysis, 57, 91–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1998). Bare Possibilia. Erkenntnis, 48, 257–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1999). Existence and contingency. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 73, 181–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). The necessary framework of objects. Topoi, 19, 201–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, D. W. (1998). Distinct discernibles and the bundle theory. In P. van Inwagen & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Metaphysics: The big questions (pp. 58–67). Malden/Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gilead, A. (2020). A Panenmentalist Reconsideration of the Identity of Indiscernibles. In: The Panenmentalist Philosophy of Science. Synthese Library, vol 424. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-41124-4_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation