Log in

Ratnakīrti and the Extent of Inner Space: an Essay on Yogācāra and the Threat of Genuine Solipsism

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Commentary to this article was published on 15 March 2019

Abstract

Though perhaps a dubious honor, Dharmakīrti (fl. c. 550–650 C.E.) is the first philosopher in any tradition to explicitly recognize the epistemological threat of solipsism, devoting an entire essay to the problem—The Justification of (the very idea of) Other Minds (Santānāntarasiddhi). This essay revisits Ratnakīrti’s (990–1050 C.E.) Doing Away with (A Justification of) Other Beings (Santānāntaraduṣaṇa) as a diagnosis of Dharmakīrti’s attempt to reconstruct the very idea of other beings, with particular attention to Ratnakīrti’s sensitivity to the conceptual preconditions for a genuine threat of solipsism. Along with the diagnosis of the conditions for the emergence of a problem of genuine solipsism, this essay takes as its focus Ratnakīrti’s criticism of attempts to meet with the problem. In particular, I shall stress an insight Ratnakīrti adduces in the course of his diagnosis. Attempts to meet the problem of solipsism head on, Ratnakīrti shows us, obscure what the preconditions for a genuine problem reveal: the fact of our possessing two incommensurable conceptions of mind, one of which is intrinsically and entirely first-personal—in a sense to be clarified in the course of this essay—and the other not. I conclude this essay with an inconclusive sketch of the difficulties that remain when considering what Ratnakīrti would have us conclude from his own diagnosis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Adapting Peter Strawson’s sense of ‘a genuine issue’ in Strawson 2011, 87.

  2. For two reasons. First, varieties of methodological solipsism influenced by Carnap involve replacing inferred entities (and concerns with the justification of inferences to such entities) with logical constructions; and, secondly, such constructions, or, equivalently, the reduction of statements about minds and other cultural objects to statements about experiences, concern ‘unowned’ experiences. See Hacker (1975, 187–8). Contrast this with the way in which genuine solipsism becomes a puzzle in Russell (1923). But see Arnold 2009 for the possibility of methodological solipsism in the tradition of Digṅāga..

  3. Perhaps first reconstructed as a single doxographical tradition by Bhāviveka, Eckel (2009, 64-65). For surveys of the different paradigms of arguments, see now Arnold (2008), Kapstein (2014), Kellner and Taber (2014), and Finnigan (2017). For some sense of the range of possible ways of formulating a restriction to the mental (including ways couched within the meditative horizon of an individual, and subsequently generalized), see Harrison (1988), 3–4.

  4. This is a rough-and-ready paraphrase of La Vallée Poussin (1928, vol. I., 430–31). See Wei Tat (1973, 523); Scharfstein (1998, f19, 421); Wood (1991, 95); Williams (2008, 98); Schmithausen (2005, 52). A similar denial is also found in Kuiji’s (K’ue-chi’s) Comprehensive Commentary on the Heart Sutra, as translated in Shih and Lusthaus (2001, 26): ‘Consciousness only (vijñapti-mātra) shows that there are definitely no dharmas apart from the mind. However, this does not mean that nothing exists except the mind, because worthy friends, causes and effects, noumena and phenomena, and conventional and ultimate are not nonexistent.’

  5. That contextualizing Yogācāra as a Buddhist therapeutic project yields a very different interpretation than others have supposed necessary is the thrust of Lusthaus (2002), Waldron (2003), and Gold (2014).

  6. Cf. Gold (2006), for a similar problem attending the interpretation of other technical terms, such as ‘grasper’ and ‘grasped,’ or terms of art such as ‘inner’ and ‘outer’ in pre-Digṅāga Yogācāra.

  7. The concession may be found in Xuanzang’s response to an earlier question, as translated by Tat (1973, 523), paragraph 7: “Who says that another person’s mind is not the object of one’s own consciousness? We only deny that it is the immediate and direct object.” See also La Vallée Poussin (1928, Vol. I., 430); See Wood (1991, 95). That is, whereas the interlocutor wants to consider other minds (and other persons) to be categorically distinct from, or at least, irreducible to, the category of intentional content, Xuanzang’s response, in effect, reiterates the sense that something counts as available only given its serving as content, and preserves other beings by appealing to a non-evident, tendentious and distinct variety of “indirect” or “remote” intentional content. On this very difficult issue of remote content, see Schmithausen (2005), taking account of views in Lusthaus (2002).

  8. It is perhaps only with Prajñākaragupta (fl. eighth century C.E.) that you get explicit mention of a thesis to this effect, given the semantic thesis that what it is ‘to exist’ means ‘being taken up as intentional content’ (as expressed in phrases such as upalambhaḥ satteti vyavasthā, upalambhaḥ satteti vyavasthā, tata upalambhaḥ sattocyate, and more, discussed in Inami (2011, 191, n49). But we can ascribe the preconditions for such a view earlier, perhaps as early as when Digṅāga takes intentional content to be entirely explicable by an inner gerundive (to adapt talk of ‘inner accusatives’ in epistemology to track Digṅāga’s talk of antar-jñeya) as in Ālambanaparīkṣā 6a–c (Frauwallner 1982, 182). For a comparative sense of the weight of Prajñākaragupta’s semantic thesis, see Ayers (1986).

  9. Given Xuanzang’s concession to something in the neighborhood of the semantic thesis that to exist is to count as intentional content, it is unclear at best whether he can justify his impatience by relying on Vasubandhu’s discussion of what, if anything, knowledge of other minds might consist in at verse 21 of the Viṃśikā (the context for Xuanzang’s discussion, as recognized already by La Vallée Poussin 1928, Vol. I., 431). For one thing, it seems to me that Vasubandhu would not concede anything to the semantic thesis. For another thing, when Vasubandhu denies that our acquaintance with our own mental states counts as knowledge in a strict sense, he might be shown to reject the preconditions for the generation of the particular problem to which Xuanzang is responding. See Kachru (2015, 333–348, 539–557); Tzohar (2010).

  10. See chapter 6 in Avramides (2001). And, Dharmakīrti’s sense is distinct as well from what ‘knowledge of other minds’ can mean given the long history of Buddhist scholasticism. For a sketch of possible meanings for which, see Kachru (2015, 543–544).

  11. I have found helpful in this respect the distinction James Conant draws between two (ideal-typical) varieties of skepticism, Cartesian and Kantian. See Conant (2012, 5–7). Also compare the distinction Avramides (2001) draws between epistemological and conceptual versions of the problem of other minds. Note that Avramides thinks that the conceptual problem went unrecognized until Wittgenstein, given that ‘on our conception of mind there is nothing in Reid’s work (Avramides 2001, 8).’

  12. The phrase ‘epistemic reduction’ is intended to invite comparison with ‘phenomenological reduction,’ while encouraging an appreciation of important differences. It is important to note that what is disclosed through Dharmakīrti’s argument is intended to serve as an evidentiary court of appeal in the epistemic justification of empirical beliefs, and is not, perhaps, entirely inconsistent with empirical descriptions of mental events as causally describable particulars.

  13. Against the thrust of such mereological arguments as are directed by Śāntarakṣita, for example, against phenomenal content, when such content is a candidate for being a concrete particular; see verses 22-49 of Madhyamakālaṃkāra, in Ichigō (1989, 199-207). I remain unsure that the best way to render this emphasis on the non-dual character of the phenomenological manifold is to say that the space of awareness—phenomenological presence—is a single kind of stuff, or mass of awareness, phenomenally variable. I do not think we should think of it as stuff at all, and thus, I do not think we should take it that Ratnakīrti would have us treat ‘mind’ as a peculiar variety of mass noun. But, I reserve this issue for the conclusion of this essay, as it will depend on what we think Ratnakīrti’s rejection of any argument that purports to show us a valid construction of the idea of other beings might mean.

  14. As one can paraphrase Ratnakīrti’s comment at the close of his essay: ‘And the way out of the dark night of Vedānta is indicated by The Commentator (Prajñākaragupta), given just so much as the possibility of manifold intentional content (Translation mine, Thakur 1957, 142).’ To appreciate Ratnakīrti’s emphasis, it is helpful to consider Vedānta’s views of consciousness as such being non-intentional and contentless, part of the source of Ratnakīrti’s pun on the word ‘dark.’ See Mohanty (1988), Ganeri (2007, 208). The historian of Buddhist philosophy might also wish to consider how such a criticism might be a deflection from the more intimate provocation provided by the views of the Buddhist Ratnākaraśānti, a philosophically trenchant characterization of whose debate with Ratnakīrti’s teacher, Jñānaśrīmitra, on just this issue may be found in Tomlinson (2018). Of course, the Buddhists seem only to have Advaita Vedānta in mind. For non-advaita views available in Vedānta, see Bilimoria and Padaki (2003). I am grateful to the editor for this reference.

  15. Note, that this question, prima facie justified on the basis of an epistemic reduction, is not one that Ratnakīrti thinks can be coherently sustained, given that it helps itself to the intelligibility of the idea of other beings. See below.

  16. For a characterization of the reasons (historical and philosophical) why Dharmakīrti’s epistemic idealism takes the form of a commitment to representationalism, see Arnold (2008), Arnold (2012, 96, 164, 174).

  17. For a recognition of the difference this might make, and the comparative consideration of Berkeley and Dharmakīrti on arguments not based on analogy, see Henkel (2012). The argument is elicited from Dharmakīrti’s interlocutor in verses 4–9 (Stcherbatsky 1969, 86–88); step 3 is discussed at length in verse 11 (Stcherbatsky 1969, 88); and the last steps in 4 are discussed by Dharmakīrti beginning in verses 13 on (Stcherbatsky 1969, 89-), taking up extremely interesting terrain concerning the presentation of semblance of actions (the general case of automata) which students of skepticism will no doubt be interested in here but which I ignore, as I do the challenge discussed in Henkel (2012), of showing the availability of this argument to both epistemological realists and idealists.

  18. For Abhinavagupta’s criticism of Dharmakīrti’s commitment to the phenomenologically implausible idea of evident but unplaced actions, see Ratié (2007).

  19. On Ratnakīrti’s designating types (such as a type x) by the locution x-mātra, see Patil 2009, 215, n44. Technically, this type is what Ratnakīrti calls a ‘horizontal general type’ (tiryag-sāmānya), on which an item is understood to be excluded from items belonging to a different class. See Patil 2009, 215–216, n44.

  20. Ontological solipsism would include any thesis to the effect that there exists only one mind, a conclusion entailed by the thought that there exists at least one mind, and that no other minds can be creditably thought to exist. Typically, those who have taken this route do not interpret that last claim as showing us that perhaps our criteria for making sense of the very idea of minds in ‘other minds/mental persons’ are lacking. See for example, Inami (2001), which would have it that Ratnakīrti, as far as other minds/mental persons go, in some straightforward sense ‘denies their existence.’ See also the introduction to Kajiyama (1965), when he says of the Saṁtānāntara-dūṣaṇa that it ‘unreservedly declares solipsism as the final destination of idealism.’ The solipsism I think he has in mind involves an ontological thesis.

  21. This is delicate. It is not clear whether or not Ratnakīrti might allow for a concept of inner space to count as an instance of a ‘vertical universal.’. I think not—for that would still require for its sense the exclusion of other particulars of the same type, which is just what Ratnakīrti thinks cannot be given a sense based on the manifest evidence of inner space. See Patil 2009, 216.

  22. I say ‘diagnostic’ to get at Ratnakīrti’s stance towards the problem of solipsism (and more about which below.) I do not, however, also mean to say that Ratnakīrti’s diagnostic stance is necessarily therapeutic, which seems at the very least to require that one links the error exposed by analysis to some further psychological factor (cf. Hacker 2007 on Gordan Baker’s therapeutic interpretation of Wittgenstein). One might adduce here Ratnakīrti’s suggestion in the Sarvajñāsiddhi that analysis ‘will also, however…in conclusion, remove the morbid and irrational longing (dohada) for sarva-sarvajña (paryante tu, sarvasarvajñadohadamapyaneṣyāmaḥ (Goodman 1989, 121; 158)).’ To link a philosophical category to a kind of irrational yet deep-seated (and psychologically recognizable) craving seems to me indicative of a therapeutic stance, but Ratnakīrti does not announce such a claim with respect to his analysis of the preconditions of solipsism as an ostensibly genuine problem.

  23. Cf. McDermott (1969, 9), who maintains that Ratnakīrti subscribes to solipsistic idealism from ‘a translogical or absolute point of view.’ I am not sure what work the qualifier ‘trans-logical’ is meant to do—it might be interesting if it is meant to indicate that we must consider the relationship between ‘intelligibility’ and ‘justification.’ Another meaning might be that all structures of justification and evidence belong to the sphere of what is conventional.

  24. At the time of this writing, I do not know if Jonardon Ganeri, speaking of Ratnakīrti’s conceptual solipsism (Ganeri 2012, 212–213)—a locution I find attractive—would agree with this way of putting it. For he also speaks of ‘a great mass of undivided cognition,’ and of consciousness which is pure and incapable of sustaining a first-personal stance (Ganeri 2012, 205). We are necessarily trading metaphors here, but I do not think that on my view, we could say with Ganeri that there is some kind of mass of consciousness, or single stuff (as in Ganeri 2007, 209).

References

  • Arnold, D. A. (2008). Buddhist idealism, epistemic and otherwise: Thoughts on the alternating perspectives of Dharmakirti. Sophia, 47(1), 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. A. (2009). Svasamvitti as methodological solipsism: “Narrow Content” and the problem of intentionality in Buddhist philosophy of mind. In M. D’Amato, J. Garfield, & T. Tillemans (Eds.), Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy (pp. 135–159). Oxford University Press.

  • Arnold, Daniel A. 2012. Brains, Buddhas and believing: The problem of intentionality in classical Buddhist and cognitive-scientific philosophy of mind. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Avramides, Anita. 2001. Other minds. Routledge. Reprint: 2009. New York and Oxon: Routledge.

  • Ayers, M. R. (1986). Berkeley and the meaning of existence. History of European Ideas, 7(6), 567–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bilimoria, P., & Padaki, S. (2003). How deep does Consciousness go? Descartes, Nyāya, Psychoanalysis, Patañjali and the Mīmāṃsaka Rāmānuja on mind-ing. In Landscape of Matter. Conference Proceedings on the Concept of Matter, pp. 49–88, Prasaranga, Bangalore University, Bangalore.

  • Chakrabarti, A. (2011). Troubles with a second self: The problem of other minds in 11th century Indian and 20th century Western philosophy. Argument, 1(1), 23–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakrabarti, A. (2016). How do we read Others’ feelings? Strawson and Zhuangzi Speak to Dharmakirti, Ratnakirti, and Abhinavagupta. In A. Chakrabarti & R. Weber (Eds.), Comparative Philosophy without Borders (pp. 95–115). London and New York: Bloomsbury.

  • Conant, J. (2012). Two Varieties of Skepticism in Rethinking Epistemology 2. In G. Abel & J. Conant (Eds.), (pp. 1–77). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckel, M. D. (2009). Bhaviveka and his Buddhist opponents: Chapters 4 and 5 of the verses on the heart of the middle way (Madhyamakahrdayakarikah) with the commentary entitled the flame of reason (Tarkajvala). Harvard Oriental Series: 70. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnigan, B. (2017). Buddhist idealism. In T. Goldschmidt & K. Pearce (Eds.), Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics (pp. 178–199). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Frauwallner, E. (1982). Kleine Schriften. In G. Oberhammer & E. Steinkellner (Eds.), Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner.

  • Ganeri, Jonardon. 2007. The concealed art of the soul: Theories of the self and practices of truth in Indian ethics and epistemology. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Ganeri, Jonardon. 2012. The self: naturalism, Consciousness, and the First-Person Stance. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Gold, J. C. (2006). No Outside, No Inside: Duality, Reality and Vasubandhu’s Illusory Elephant. Asian Philosophy, 16(1), 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, J. C. (2014). Paving the great way: Vasubandhu’s unifying Buddhist philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Goodman, Steven B. 1989. ‘A Buddhist proof for omniscience: The “Sarvajñasiddhi” of Ratnakīrti,’ PhD Dissertation, Temple University.

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1975). Insight and illusion: Wittgenstein on philosophy and the metaphysics of experience. Oxford, London, and New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). Gordan Baker’s Late interpretation of Wittgenstein. In G. Kahane, E. Kanterian, & O. Kuusela (Eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker (pp. 88–122). Malden and Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Hacking, Ian. (2004). Historical Ontology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

  • Harrison, P. (1988). The Pratyutpanna Samādhi Sutra. In BDK English Tripitaka 25-II, 25-III (pp. 1–115). Berkeley: Numata Center for Buddhist Translation and Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkel, J. E. (2012). How to avoid solipsism while remaining an idealist: Lessons from Berkeley and Dharmakīrti. Comparative Philosophy, 3(1), 58–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hidenori, K. (1955). A refutation of Solipsism: Annotated translation of Saṃtānāntarasiddhi. Journal of the Greater India Society, 14(1), 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichigō, M. (1989). Śāntarakṣita’s Madhyamakālaṃkāra. In L. O. Gómez & J. A. Silk (Eds.), Studies in the Literature of the Great Vehicle. Michigan Studies in Buddhist Literature No. 1 (pp. 141–240). Ann Arbor: Collegiate Institute for the Study of Buddhist Literature and Center for South and Southeast Asian Studies. The University of Michigan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inami, M. (2001). The problem of other minds in the Buddhist epistemological tradition. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 29(2001), 465–483. Wien: Verlag der Österreichen Akademie der Wissenschaften.

  • Inami, M. (2011). Nondual cognition. In H. Lasic, E. Franco, & B. Kellner (Eds.), Religion and Logic in Buddhist Philosophical Analysis, Proceedings of the Fourth International Dharmakīrti Conference in Vienna, August 23–27, 2005. Wien (pp. 177–196).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kachru, Sonam. 2015. Minds and worlds: A philosophical commentary on the twenty verses of Vasubandhu. PhD Dissertation, University of Chicago.

  • Kajiyama, Y. (1965). Buddhist solipsism: A free translation of Ratnakīrti’s Saṃtānāntaradūṣaṇa. Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies/Indogaku Bukkyōgaku Kenkyū, 13(1), 435–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapstein, M. T. (2014). Buddhist idealists and their Jain Critics on Our Knowledge of External Objects. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 74, 123–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellner, B., & Taber, J. (2014). Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda Idealism I: The interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā. Asiatische Studien, 68(3), 709–756.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kremer, M. (2004). To what extent is solipsism a truth? In B. Stocker (Ed.), Post-Analytic Tractatus (pp. 59–84). Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Vallée Poussin, Louis de. 1928. Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi: La Siddhi de Hiuan-Tsang. Paris: Librairie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner.

  • Lusthaus, D. (2002). Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun. New York: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, A. C. (1969). An Eleventh-Century Buddhist Logic of ‘Exists’: Ratnakīrti’s Kṣaṇabhaṅgasiddhiḥ Vyatirekātmikā. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

  • Mohanty, J. N. (1988). Consciousness in Vedānta. In P. T. Raju (Ed.), Perspectives on Vedānta: Essays in Honor of Professor P. T. Raju. Leiden; New York: E. J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuttall, A. D. (1974). A common sky: Philosophy and the literary imagination. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patil, Parimal G. (2009). Against a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Ratié, I. (2007). Otherness in the Pratyabhijñā philosophy. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 35, 313–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1923). Vagueness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, I(2), 84–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadhukan, S. K. (1990). The conflict between the Buddhist and the Naiyayika philosophers: A brief survey. Bulletin of Tibetology, 1–3, 39–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharfstein, B.-A. (1998). A comparative history of world Philosophy from the Upaniṣads to Kant. Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmithausen, L. (2005). On the problem of the external world in the Ch’eng wei shih Lun. (Studia Philological Buddhica Occasional Paper Series, XIII). Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shih, H.-c., & Lusthaus, D. (2001). A comprehensive commentary on the heart Sutra (Prajñāpārāmita-Hṛdaya-Sūtra). Translated from the Chinese of K’ue-chi (Taisho Volume 33, Number 1710). Berkeley: Numata Center for Buddhist Translation and Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stcherbatsky, Th. 1969. ‘Establishment of the existence of other minds: Annotated translation of Saṃtānāntarasiddhi. A free translation of Dharmakīrti’s Santānāntarasiddhi with Vinītadeva’s Santānāntarasiddhiṭīkā.’ In Papers of Th. Stcherbatsky: Translated for the First Time into English by Hasrish. C. Gupta, Edited with an Introduction by Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya, edited by Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya, translated by Hasrish. C. Gupta, 81–121. Soviet Indology Series 2. Calcutta: Indian Studies Past and Present.

  • Strawson, P. (2011). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. First published in 1959. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tat, W. (1973. (Trans.)). Ch’eng Wei-Shih Lun: The doctrine of mere-consciousness by Hsüan-Tsang. Hong Kong: The Ch’eng Wei-Shih Lun Publication Committee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thakur, A. (1957). Ratnakīrti-nibandhāvalī: (Buddhist Nyāya Works of Ratnakīrti). Deciphered and ed. TSWS, Tibetan Sanskrit Works Series 3 (1st ed.). Patna: K. P. Jayaswal Research Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, J. (2010). Mill’s argument for other minds. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 9(3), 507–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomlinson, D. K. (2018). The tantric context of Ratnākaraśānti’s philosophy of mind. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 46(2), 355–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tzohar, R. (2010). Questioning the other, questioning oneself: Other minds in Vasubandhu’s treatise in twenty verses (Viṃśatikākārikā-Vṛtti). In P. Ghosh (Ed.), Materialism and Immaterialism in India and the West: Varying Vistas, (Project of History of Indian Science), Philosophy and Culture Series (Vol. XII, pp. 69–79). New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, W. S. (2003). The Buddhist unconscious: The Alaya-vijnana in the context of Indian Buddhist thought. Routledge Curzon.

  • Watson, Alex. 2006. The self’s awareness of itself: Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha’s arguments against the Buddhist doctrine of no-self. Wien: Sammlung de Nobili, Institut für Südasien-, Tibet-, und Buddhismuskunde der Universität Wien.

  • Williams, P. (2008). Mahāyāna Buddhism: The doctrinal foundations (Second ed.). London and New York: Routledge.

  • Wood, T. E. (1991). Mind only: A philosophical and doctrinal analysis of the Vijñānavāda. Monographs of the Society for Asian and Comparative Philosophy 9. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sonam Kachru.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This submission is intended as part of the special issue on Yogācāra guest edited by Roy Tzohar.

A comment to this article is available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-019-0724-7.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kachru, S. Ratnakīrti and the Extent of Inner Space: an Essay on Yogācāra and the Threat of Genuine Solipsism. SOPHIA 58, 61–83 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-019-0707-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-019-0707-8

Keywords

Navigation