Log in

The Puzzling Resilience of Multiple Realization

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to the multiple realization argument, mental states or processes can be realized in diverse and heterogeneous physical systems; and that fact implies that mental state or process kinds cannot be identified with particular kinds of physical states or processes. More specifically, mental processes cannot be identified with brain processes. Moreover, the argument provides a general model for the autonomy of the special sciences. The multiple realization argument is widely influential, but over the last thirty years it has also faced serious objections. Despite those objections, most philosophers regard the fact of multiple realization and the cogency of the multiple realization argument as plainly correct. Why is that? What is it about the multiple realization argument that makes it so resilient? One reason is that the multiple realization argument is deeply intertwined with a view that minds are, in some sense, computational. But we argue that the sense in which minds are computational does not support the conclusion that they are ipso facto multiply realized. We argue that the sense in which brains compute does not imply that brains implement multiply realizable computational processes, and it does not provide a general model for the autonomy of the special sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Such claims are difficult to adjudicate, of course. But it is telling that even critics of multiple realization tend to comment on its widespread acceptance. Ned Block (1997) writes, “For nearly thirty years, there has been a consensus (at least in English-speaking countries) that reductionism is a mistake and that there are autonomous special sciences. This consensus has been based on an argument from multiple realizability” (1997: 107). Jaegwon Kim, in his Philosophy of Mind textbook writes, “by the mid-1970s most philosophers had abandoned reductionist physicalism, not only as a view about psychology but as a doctrine about the special sciences… All this stemmed from a single idea: the multiple realizability of mental properties” (2011: 129, italics removed.) And John Bickle, in his Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Multiple Realizability, remarks on “the still-too-prominent view in the philosophy of mind that multiple realization spells doom for reductive materialism and mind-brain identity theory once and for all” (2020). It is telling that of the 79 essays in the second edition of David Chalmers’ Philosophy of Mind anthology (2022), fewer than a half dozen seriously consider views according to which multiple realization is false, and they were all originally published over 40 years ago.

  2. A referee suggested sociological reasons for philosophers’ ready acceptance of multiple realization – a tendency to jump on the bandwagon, especially when its drivers are charismatic figures like Putnam and Fodor. We do not wish to dismiss this possibility, but we choose to focus on philosophical justifications for the continuing popularity of the thesis. Why is the idea of multiple realization so easy to sell? Surely, if pressed, advocates of multiple realization would sooner appeal to philosophical justifications than to sociological ones, even if (as the referee suggests) the sociological reasons might be an important tacit cause. Our question is whether such philosophical justifications are cogent, apart from whether they are the “real” motivators.

  3. We don’t deny that there may be other possible sources; we only propose that this is an important one. Some candidates for accounts of multiple realization that do not overly appeal to considerations of computational abstraction, e.g., the subset view (Wilson, 1999, 2011) or the dimensioned view (Aizawa & Gillett, 2009a, b, 2011). But notice that both of those views are broadly reductive, and therefore do not purport to provide an account of the “autonomy” of the special sciences in the manner that Fodor requires.

  4. Though we cannot pursue the question here, we have doubts about whether motivations for functionalism are ever fully independent of considerations of multiple realizability.

  5. The “only game in town” idea was assailed as early as Dennett (1983) and Kosslyn and Hatfield (1984); and then more vigorously with the advent of connectionist alternatives (Hatfield, 1991).

  6. For surveys, see Aizawa (2010); Miłkowski (2013a; Piccinini (2015).

  7. In contrast, Lewis (1972) coins the term “multiple realization” by way of expressing the concern that if the descriptions do not have unique realizers then they are “improper” descriptions that “do not (in any normal way) name anything here in our actual world” (1972: 252).

  8. If, as is common in recent literature, the realization relation is itself understood in terms of causal inheritance, as in the subset view (Wilson, 1999, 2011) or dimensioned view (Gillett, 2002), then abstract computational states are not even candidates for realization. Whether this is a defect in those accounts is a matter of dispute.

  9. This is closely related to what Lawrence Shapiro (2004) calls the Mental Constraint Thesis.

  10. And that should be no surprise because Piccinini explicitly aims to assimilate computational explanation to mechanistic explanation (2015, 2020; see also Piccinini & Craver 2011).

  11. Piccinini is aware of this issue (Piccinini & Boone, 2016).

  12. Notice that the economic example also has the feature emphasized by Chirimuuta (2021): what counts as a “monetary exchange” or “financial transaction” is dependent on human beings and our interests. The fact that anything could be used as a currency is just the fact that anything can be used as a conventional or arbitrary representation — that is, used by us to represent, given the right circumstances.

  13. Compare the debate over whether the Principle of Natural Selection is an empirical law or a trivial theorem of probability theory (e.g., Brandon 1990).

References

  • Aizawa, K. 2010. Computation in Cognitive Science: It is Not All About Turing-Equivalent Computation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41: 227–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. and C. Gillett. 2009a. The (Multiple) Realization of Psychological and Other Properties in the Sciences. Mind and Language, 24: 181–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. and C. Gillett. 2009b. Levels, Individual Variation, and Massive Multiple Realization in Neurobiology. In J. Bickle (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press: 529–581.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. and C. Gillett. 2011. The Autonomy of Psychology in the Age of Neuroscience. In Phyllis McKay Illari Federica Russo (Eds.), Causality in the Sciences. Oxford University Press: 202–223.

  • Appiah, K. A. 2017. As If. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. and J. Mundale. 1999. Multiple Realizability Revisited: Linking Cognitive and Neural States. Philosophy of Science, 66: 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 1998. Psychoneural Reduction. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2003. Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, MA.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2010. Has the Last Decade of Challenges to the Multiple Realization Argument Provided Aid and Comfort to Psychoneural Reductionists? Synthese. 177: 247–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2020. Multiple Realizability. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Eds.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/multiple-realizability/.

  • Block, N. 1997. Antireductionism Slaps Back. Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 107–132.

  • Block, N. and J. Fodor. 1972. What Psychological States are Not. Philosophical Review 8: 159–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1990. Adaptation and Environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cao, R. 2018. Computational Explanations and Neural Coding. In Sprevak and Colombo (Eds.), Routledge Handbook of the Computational Brain. New York: Routledge, 2018: 283–296.

  • Cao, R. 2022. Multiple Realizability and the Spirit of Functionalism. Synthese, 200 (6):1–31.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. 1996. Does a Rock Implement Every Finite-State Automaton? Synthese, 108: 310–333.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 2022. Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Second Edition). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Chirimuuta, M. 2014. Minimal Models and Canonical Neural Computations: The Distinctness of Computational Explanation in Neuroscience. Synthese, 191 (2): 127–153.

  • Chirimuuta, M. 2021. Your Brain Is Like a Computer: Function, Analogy, Simplification. In F. Calzavarini, M. Viola (Eds.), Neural Mechanisms, Studies in Brain and Mind 17: 235–260.

  • Craver, C. 2004. Dissociable Realization and Kind Splitting. Philosophy of Science, 71: 960–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. 1989. Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1983. Styles of Mental Representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83: 213–226.

  • Enç, B. 1983. In Defense of the Identity Theory. Journal of Philosophy, 80: 279 – 98.

  • Fodor, J. 1974. Special sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis. Synthese, 28: 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1975. The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Crowell and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1997. Special sciences: Still Autonomous After All These Years. In Tomberlin, J. (Eds.), Philosophical Perspectives 11: Mind, Causation, and World. Boston: Blackwell Publishers (1997).

  • Gillett, C. 2002. The Dimensions of Realization: A Critique of the Standard View. Analysis, 62 (4): 316–323.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. 1991. Representation in Perception and Cognition: Connectionist Affordances. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, (Eds.), W. Ramsey, S. Stich and D. Rummelhart (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 163–195.

  • Hemmo, M. and O. Shenker. 2015. The Emergence of Macroscopic Regularity. Mind and Society, 14 (2): 221–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T. 2004. Special Sciences: Still a Flawed Argument After All These Years. Cognitive Science, 28: 409–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1972. Phenomenal Properties, Psychophysical Laws, and Identity Theory. Monist 56, 2: 177–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1993. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 2011. Philosophy of Mind (Third Edition). Philadelphia, PA: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1984. 1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences. Philosophical Review, 93 (3): 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. and Hatfield, G. 1984. Representation without Symbol Systems. Social Research, 51: 1019–1045.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. 2016. Because Without Cause: Non-Causal Explanations in Science and Mathematics. Oxford. UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, J. 2008. Functionalism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Eds.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/functionalism/.

  • Lewis, D. 1969. Review of Art, Mind, and Religion. Journal of Philosophy, 66: 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1972. Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50:249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. 1974. Mental States and Putnam’s Functionalist Hypothesis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 52: 48–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maimon, A. and M. Hemmo. 2022. Does Neuroplasticity Support the Hypothesis of Multiple Realizability? Philosophy of Science, 8: 107–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maley, C. forthcoming. Medium Independence and the Failure of the Mechanistic Account of Computation. Ergo.

  • Marr, D. 1982. Vision. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miłkowski, M. 2013a. Explaining the Computational Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Milkowski, M. 2013b. A Mechanistic Account of Computational Explanation in Cognitive Science. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, & I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Cooperative Minds: Social Interaction and Group Dynamics. Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society): 3050–3055.

  • Piccinini, G. 2015. Physical Computation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. 2020. Neurocognitive Mechanisms: Explaining Biological Cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. and S. Bahar. 2013. Neural Computation and the Computational Theory of Cognition. Cognitive Science, 37 (3): 453–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. and T. Boone. 2016. Mechanistic Abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83: (5) 686–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. and C. Craver. 2011. Integrating Psychology and Neuroscience: Functional Analyses as Mechanism Sketches. Synthese, 183: 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. and A. Scarantino. 2011. Information Processing, Computation, and Cognition. Journal of Biological Physics 37 (1):1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. and O. Shagrir. 2014. Foundations of Computational Neuroscience. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 25 (2014): 25–30.

  • Polger, T. 2002. Putnam’s Intuition. Philosophical Studies, 109 (2): 143–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. 2004a. Natural Minds. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. 2004b. Neural Machinery and Realization. Philosophy of Science, 71 (5): 997–1006.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. 2007a. Realization and the Metaphysics of Mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85 (2): 233–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. 2009a. Evaluating the Evidence for Multiple Realization. Synthese, 167 (3): 457–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. 2009b. Two Confusions Concerning Multiple Realizability. Philosophy of Science, 75 (5): 537–547.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. and L. Shapiro. 2016. The Multiple Realization Book. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1967. Psychological Predicates. Reprinted as “The Nature of Mental States” in H. Putnam (Eds.), 1975.

  • Putnam, H. 1973. Philosophy and Our Mental Life. Reprinted in H. Putnam (Ed.), 1975.

  • Putnam, H. 1973. Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, 2: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1988. Representation and Reality. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R. 1979. Functionalism and Reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 46: 533–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, 2009. Multiple Realization and Methodological Pluralism. Synthese, 167 (3): 473–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheutz, M. 1998. Implementation: Computationalism’s Weak Spot. Conceptus, 31: 229–39.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Scheutz, M. 1999. When Physical Systems Realize Functions. Minds and Machines, 9: 161–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2000. Multiple Realizations. Journal of Philosophy, 97 (12):635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2004. The Mind Incarnate. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2008. How to Test for Multiple Realization. Philosophy of Science, 75 (5):514–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2010. Lessons from Causal Exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81: 594–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart J. J. C. 1959. Sensations and Brain Processes. Philosophical Review, LXVIII: 141–156.

  • Sober, E. 1999. The Multiple Realizability Argument Against Reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 66: 542–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2022. Energy Requirements Undermine Substrate Independence and Mind-Body Functionalism. Philosophy of Science, 89: 70–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. 1950. Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind, LIX:(236), 433–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R. 1988. Consciousness, Intrinsic Intentionality, and Self-Understanding Machines. In Consciousness in Contemporary Science, (Eds.), A. J. Marcel and E. Bisiach, (Oxford University Press: Oxford) 78–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. 2007. Three Kinds of Idealization. Journal of Philosophy. 104 (12):639–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. 1999. How Superduper does a Physicalist Supervenience Need to Be? The Philosophical Quarterly 49: 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. 2011. Non-Reductive Realization and the Powers-based Subset Strategy. The Monist. 94: No. 1, Powers (January 2011), pp. 121–154.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to two anonymous referees for comments that substantially improved this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas W. Polger.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Polger, T.W., Shapiro, L.A. The Puzzling Resilience of Multiple Realization. Minds & Machines 33, 321–345 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-023-09635-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-023-09635-z

Keywords

Navigation