Log in

Paradoxicality Without Paradox

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is not uncommon among theorists favoring a deviant logic on account of the semantic paradoxes to subscribe to an idea that has come to be known as ‘classical recapture’. The main thought underpinning it is that non-classical logicians are justified in endorsing many instances of the classically valid principles that they reject. Classical recapture promises to yield an appealing pair of views: one can attain naivety for semantic concepts while retaining classicality in ordinary domains such as mathematics. However, Julien Murzi and Lorenzo Rossi have recently suggested that revisionary approaches to truth breed revenge paradoxes when they are coupled with the thought that classical reasoning can be recaptured in certain circumstances. What’s novel about the paradoxes they put forward is that they cannot be dismissed so easily. The concepts used to generate these paradoxes—those of paradoxicality and unparadoxicality—are concepts that non-classical theorists need in order to offer a diagnosis of the truth-theoretic paradoxes. My goal in this paper is to argue that non-classical theorists can represent the concept of paradoxicality without falling prey to revenge paradoxes. In particular, I will show how to provide a formal fixed-point semantics for a language extended with a paradoxicality predicate that adequately expresses the non-classical logician’s notion of paradoxicality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Spain)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Their main argument is presented in Murzi and Rossi (2020a), although they have developed similar objections against non-classical accounts of the paradoxes elsewhere, cf. Rossi (2019), Murzi and Rossi (2020b). They articulate their favored view on the semantic paradoxes—a form of contextualism that retains classical logic by postulating a context shift in paradoxical arguments—in Murzi and Rossi (2018).

  2. Murzi and Rossi are not the only ones that have criticized the recapturing strategy. In fact, it wouldn’t be too exaggerated to say that this idea has come under heavy fire in the last few years. See, for example, Woods (2019), Williamson (2018), and Halbach and Nicolai (2018) for various related objections. I’ve addressed Williamson’s charges in Rosenblatt (xxxx) and Woods’ criticism in Rosenblatt (2021). A reply to Halbach and Nicolai’s challenge can be found in Hartry Field’s Field (2021).

  3. Prominent supporters of paracompleteness include Field (2008) and Horsten (2011). I hasten to say that some of the arguments to be offered below—though not all of them—are to some extent independent of the specific approach under consideration, and I suspect that the modifications that would be needed to accommodate some of the other approaches criticized by Murzi and Rossi shouldn’t be too substantial. At any rate, I will briefly return to this issue below (see Footnote 24).

  4. Murzi and Rossi actually rely on the stronger assumption that for any open formula \(\phi (x)\) there is a term t such that \(t = \ulcorner \phi (t)\urcorner \) is provable, but the interderivability between \(\psi \) and \(\phi \ulcorner \psi \urcorner \) is enough for their purposes.

  5. Murzi and Rossi employ multisets—rather than sets—because non-contractive approaches are among their targets. A multiset is just like a set except for the fact that it is sensitive to different occurrences of the same member.

  6. To be sure, other paracomplete logicians might jettison some of these rules. For example, relevant logicians endorsing a paracomplete theory will balk at the rule \(\rightarrow \)-in\(_{-}\), since it embodies a form of weakening.

  7. I am understanding \(\bot \) as a trivializing nullary connective. This means that, by definition, \(\bot \) entails any statement. Given that the consequence relation is transitive, it follows that for any \(\Gamma \), if \(\Gamma \vdash \bot \), then \(\Gamma \vdash \phi \) for any statement \(\phi \).

  8. Note that in Murzi and Rossi’s derivation, as well as in the derivation below, only \(\rightarrow \)-in\(_{W}\) is used.

  9. Cf. (Murzi and Rossi 2020a, p. 162).

  10. What is typically meant by a notion being ‘merely instrumental’ is that the notion shouldn’t be seen as carving out a bona-fide semantic category, but rather as a tool that allows the non-classical theorist to prove that her theory is not trivial.

  11. See Rosenblatt (2020) for more details. This non-uniqueness result is reminiscent of Van McGee’s well-known theorem that there is no unique maximal consistent set of instances of Tarski’s schema, cf. McGee (1992).

  12. There are yet other versions of classical recapture that are in principle available to her, cf. Rosenblatt (2020).

  13. In fact, Murzi and Rossi have suggested this idea in conversation.

  14. A similar argument is usually offered to show that one also needs an unrestricted introduction rule licensing the step from \(\psi \) to \(Tr\ulcorner \psi \urcorner \).

  15. I owe thanks to Julien Murzi and Lorenzo Rossi for raising this objection.

  16. The contents of this section partially overlap with Sect. 4 of another paper of mine, Rosenblatt (xxxx). However, the emphasis there was not on the notion of paradoxicality. My aim was to show how to provide a formal fixed-point semantics for a language containing a predicate standing for the concept of groundedness. The construction to be offered below for the paradoxicality predicate results from a straightforward adaptation of the semantics I gave in that paper for the groundedness predicate.

  17. Of course, min and max stand for the minimum and the maximum operations, respectively.

  18. Cf. his Yablo (2003). Yablo’s paper is a critique of Field’s paracomplete approach to paradoxes.

  19. The idea of applying Yablo’s technique to provide a model-theoretic treatment of a sentence-classifying (unary) operator in the context of a (broadly) Kripkean theory of truth is not new. In a previous piece I’ve suggested that it is possible to define a ‘pathologicality’ operator along these lines (see Rosenblatt and Szmuc 2014) and in another paper I show that one can have a ‘hypodoxicality’ predicate alongside Par(x), which is supposed to apply to statements like the truth-teller and its ilk (cf. Gallovich and Rosenblatt, 2021) Also, Roy Cook and Nicholas Tourville have recently provided a much more systematic study of intensional operators within the fixed-point approach (see Cook and Tourville (2018)). The main philosophical idea underpinning their account—namely, that a theory of truth capable of making intensional distinctions is desirable—is one that I am completely on board with.

  20. Rest assured, I am not claiming that this is the only notion of validity available, but this is arguably the notion that best fits the paracomplete account.

  21. According to the definition of paradoxicality provided above, there are unparadoxical statements \(\phi \) such that \(\lnot Par\ulcorner \phi \urcorner \) has value \(\frac{1}{2}\) at \(v^{FP}\). The truth-teller—a statement \(\tau \), saying of itself that it is true, \(Tr\ulcorner \tau \urcorner \)—is a case in point. Even thought it is not the case that \(\tau \) is \(\frac{1}{2}\) at every interpretation extending \(v^{FP}\), \(v^{FP}(Par\ulcorner \tau \urcorner ) =\frac{1}{2}\). But this ought not be too surprising. In this setting one shouldn’t expect the paradoxicality predicate to behave bivalently.

  22. The proofs of all these facts are straightforward applications of the definition of validity and of the definitions of the logical connectives, so I omit them.

  23. For example, I haven’t considered how paradoxicality interacts with disjunction, the conditional, or the quantifiers. In addition, I haven’t analyzed how far they can be iterated, nor do I know if some of the validities that fail could be recovered in some special cases. All these questions are interesting and deserve to be investigated; unfortunately, they are beyond the scope of this paper.

  24. Before moving on, let me stress that the fixed-point semantics offered in this section was only intended to show how to characterize a paradoxicality predicate in a paracomplete setting. So a natural question is whether it is possible to offer a similar construction for the other approaches criticized by Murzi and Rossi. The answer to this is not at all obvious, and it will likely depend on the specificities of the account under discussion. In the case of non-reflexive accounts (see French 2016; Negri 2018, Fjellstad (2015).) the modifications that would be needed to offer a similar characterization of paradoxicality are, as far as I can see, fairly minimal. As for paraconsistent and non-transitive accounts (see e.g. Beall 2009; Ripley 2012, respectively), the crucial notion—i.e. the notion that allegedly cannot be expressed on pain of triviality—is not paradoxicality, but unparadoxicality. So the challenge, in those cases, would be to provide a fixed-point semantics for a language containing an unparadoxicality predicate. Lastly, non-contractive accounts present an additional complication. Some of these accounts (cf. Zardini 2011) lack a suitable semantic characterization, and thus a Kripke-like construction is not at present available for them (though I hasten to say that other non-contractive theories of truth do enjoy a model-theoretic characterization, see Rosenblatt 2019a and Rosenblatt (2019b)). To be sure, these remarks are somewhat superficial, but there is no space here to dig deeper. The task of rigorously adapting the fixed-point semantic to these other approaches must be left for another day.

  25. As Murzi and Rossi (2020a, p. 154) put it: “From a revisionary perspective, the most natural way out of the problem is to treat the new paradoxes in the same way as the paradoxes of truth”.

  26. Cf. Priest’s 1994.

  27. One attempt at making this notion precise is given by Priest himself. His well-known ‘Inclosure-Schema’ can be used to suggest that if two paradoxes fit the schema, then they should receive the same type of solution. However, the jury is still out on whether this is a good way of capturing the thought underpinning the Principle of Uniform Solution. For a discussion of this issue and an interesting objection to Inclosure, see Beall (2014).

  28. I am indebted to Julien Murzi for discussion of this issue.

  29. In connection to this, see the final chapter of Gupta and Belnap (1993). I owe thanks to Pepe Martínez for a useful conversation about this.

  30. This is what (Beall 2009, p. 66) calls the ‘exhaustive characterization project’. In his words, this project consists in “explain[ing] how, if at all, we can truly characterize—specify the ‘semantic status’ of—all statements of our language (in our language)”.

  31. Of course, these replies are only tentative and merely scratch the surface of the matter, but the issue is large and goes beyond the scope of the paper.

References

  • Beall, J. C. (2009). Spandrels of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C. (2014). End of inclosure. Mind, 123(491), 829–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. T. &  Tourville, N. (2018). Embracing intensionality: Paradoxicality and semi-truth operators in fixed point models. Logic Journal of the IGPL.

  • Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2021). The power of Naive truth. The Review of Symbolic Logic (forthcoming).

  • Fjellstad, A. (2015). How a semantics for tonk should be. The Review of Symbolic Logic (forthcoming).

  • French, R. (2016). Structural reflexivity and the paradoxes of self-reference. Ergo, 3, 113–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, A., & Belnap, N. (1993). The revision theory of truth. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., & Nicolai, C. (2018). On the costs of nonclassical logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 227–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L. (2011). The Tarskian turn: Deflationism and axiomatic truth. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (1992). Maximal consistent sets of instances of Tarski’s schema. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21(3), 235–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murzi, J., & Rossi, L. (2018). Reflection principles and the liar in context. Philosopher’s Imprint, 18(15), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murzi, J., & Rossi, L. (2020). Generalized revenge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98(1), 153–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murzi, J., & Rossi, L. (2020). Non-contractability and revenge. Erkenntnis, 85, 905–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murzi, J., & Rossi, L. (2020). Non-reflexivity and revenge. Journal of Philosophical Logic (forthcoming).

  • Negri, S. (2018). Principles for object-linguistic consequence: From logical to irreflexive. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47(3), 549–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1994). The structure of the paradoxes of self-reference. Mind, 103(409), 25–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with transparent truth. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 354–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, L. (2019). Non-contractive classical logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 60(4), 559–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, L. (2020). Maximal non-trivial sets of instances of your least favorite logical principle. The Journal of Philosophy, 117(1), 30–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, L. (2021). Recapture results and classical logic. typescript.

  • Rosenblatt, L. (2020). Classical recapture and maximality. Philosophical Studies (forthcoming).

  • Rosenblatt, L. (2019b). On structural contraction and why it fails. Synthese (forthcoming).

  • Rosenblatt, L. Should the Non-Classical Logician be Embarrassed? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, forthcoming.

  • Rosenblatt, L., & Szmuc, D. (2014). On Pathological Truths. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 7(4), 601–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, L. (2019). Model-theoretic semantics and revenge paradoxes. Philosophical Studies, 176(4), 1035–10541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2018). Alternative Logics and Applied Mathematics. Philosophical Issues, 28(1), 399–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2019). Logical Partisanhood. Philosophical Studies, 176, 1203–1224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. New grounds for naive truth. In J.C. Beall, editor, Liars and Heaps. Oxford University Press, 2003.

  • Zardini, E. (2011). Truth Without Contra(di)ction. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(4), 498–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucas Rosenblatt.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

A talk based on an earlier version of this paper was given in 2020 at the SeloI online seminar. I am grateful to all its participants for a very stimulating discussion. Special thanks go to Eduardo Barrio, Jonas Becker Arenhart, Pablo Cobreros, Bruno Da Ré, Pepe Martínez, Federico Pailos, and Damián Szmuc. I also owe thanks to Camila Gallovich for many useful conversations about paradoxicality. Finally, I am deeply indebted to Julien Murzi and Lorenzo Rossi not only for numerous comments and various illuminating exchanges on the contents of the paper, but also for their encouragement and open-mindedness throughout the process of writing it. Financial support for this work was provided by the project “Logic and Substructurality” (FFI2017-84805-P), funded by the Spanish MINECO (Ministerio de Economía, Industria y Competitividad)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosenblatt, L. Paradoxicality Without Paradox. Erkenn 88, 1347–1366 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00405-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00405-w

Navigation