International Cooperation and Institution Formation: A Game Theoretic Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Games of Conflict and Cooperation in Asia

Part of the book series: The Political Economy of the Asia Pacific ((PEAP))

  • 492 Accesses

Abstract

Game theory presents a useful analytical tool for addressing the problem of international cooperation and the formation of institutions. We first examine four problems that must be solved to achieve international cooperation: the common knowledge problem, agreement problem, compliance problem, and participation problem. An institution is a mechanism used to enforce participants to cooperate for collective benefits. We consider a multi-stage game model of institution formation and show that a group of participants voluntarily forms an institution for international cooperation in a strict subgame perfect equilibrium if and only if the group satisfies the criticality condition. Some of the implications on the international frameworks that attempt to prevent the proliferation of nuclear weapons in East Asia are finally discussed.

I would like to thank Motoshi Suzuki and members of the Workshop on International Political and Economic Analysis for their valuable suggestions and comments. Financial support from the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science under Grant No. (A)26245020 is gratefully acknowledged.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 85.59
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 106.99
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 106.99
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an excellent survey of game theoretical works on peace and war, see O’Neill (1994).

  2. 2.

    Okada (2014) reviews recent works on game theoretical analyses of cooperation and the formation of institutions.

  3. 3.

    The text of the agreement can be found at http://www.iaea.org/Publications/Documents/Infcircs/Others/infcirc457.pdf (accessed 3 November 2014).

  4. 4.

    The text of the statement can be found at http://www.mofa.go.jp/region/asia-paci/n_korea/6party/joint0509.html (accessed 3 November 2014).

  5. 5.

    Huntley (2007) and Wit (2007) provide strategic analyses of US policy towards North Korea after the stalemate of the Six Party Talks.

  6. 6.

    An event A is called common knowledge among players if everyone knows A, everyone knows that everyone knows A, everyone knows that everyone knows that everyone knows A, ⋯ .

  7. 7.

    Okada (2003, 2007) considers an initial allocation of emissions in the Kyoto Protocol according to cooperative and non-cooperative game models.

  8. 8.

    The full text of the agreement can be found at http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/cop6secpart/05.pdf

  9. 9.

    The full text of the accords can be found at http://unfccc.int/cop7/documents/accords-draft.pdf

  10. 10.

    This game is called a linear public goods game since the supply of public goods in the payoff function (6.1) is linear in total contributions. Other types of public goods include best shot public goods and weakest link public goods. For example, Okada (2008) considers a Cobb–Douglas utility function in a public goods game with capital accumulation.

  11. 11.

    Each country i receives an additional payoff a i if it increases one unit of contributions.

  12. 12.

    As a regularity condition, we assume that 1∕a i is not an integer for any i ∈ N.

  13. 13.

    According to the IAEA document, ‘In the event of non-compliance and failure by the recipient State or States to take requested corrective steps within a reasonable time, [the IAEA is able] to suspend or terminate assistance and withdraw any materials and equipment made available by the Agency or a member in furtherance of the project’ (ARTICLE XII:A7). Please see http://www.iaea.org/About/statute.html for more details.

  14. 14.

    The aim of the DSB is to ‘maintain surveillance of implementation of rulings and recommendations, and authorize suspension of concession and other obligations under the covered agreements’. (WTO Agreement, ANNEX 2, Article 2). Please see http://www.wto.org/english/docs_e/legal_e/final_e.htm

  15. 15.

    Okada (1993) considers a mixed strategy equilibrium in the institution formation game.

References

  • Bates, R. H. (1988). Contra contractarianism: Some reflections on the new institutionalism. Politics and Society, 16, 387–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chayes, A., & Chayes, A. H. (1993). On compliance. International Organization, 47, 175–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., & Maskin, E. (1986). The folk theorem in repeated games with discounting or with incomplete information. Econometrica, 54, 533–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1967, 1968). Games with incomplete information played by ‘Bayesian’ players, Parts I–III. Management Science, 14, 159–182, 320–334, 486–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntley, W. L. (2007). U.S. policy toward north Korea in strategic context. Asian Survey, 47, 455–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld, M., Okada, A., & Riedl, A. (2009). Institution formation in public goods games. American Economic Review, 99, 1335–1355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D., & Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and decisions: Introduction and critical survey. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maruta, T., & Okada, A. (2012). Dynamic group formation in the repeated prisoner’s dilemma. Games and Economic Behavior, 74, 269–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, D. C. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5, 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okada, A. (1993). The possibility of cooperation in an n-person prisoners’ dilemma with institutional arrangements. Public Choice, 77, 629–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okada, A. (2003). A market game analysis of international CO2 emissions trading: Evaluating initial allocation rules. In: T. Sawa (Ed.), International frameworks and technological strategies to prevent climate change (pp. 3–21). Tokyo: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okada, A. (2007). International negotiations on climate change: A noncooperative game analysis of the Kyoto protocol. In: R. Avenhaus & I. W. Zartman (Eds.), Diplomacy games (pp. 231–250). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Okada, A. (2008). The second-order dilemma of public goods and capital accumulation. Public Choice, 135, 165–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okada, A. (2014). Cooperation and institution in games. Discussion paper No. 2014–11, Department of Economics, Hitotsubashi University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, P. (1980). Rewards and punishments as selective incentives for collective action: Theoretical investigations. American Journal of Sociology, 85, 1356–1375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, B. (1994). Game theory models of peace and war. In: R. J. Aumann & S. Hart (Eds.), Handbook of game theory with economic applications (Vol. 2, pp. 995–1053). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1937). The structure of social action. New York: MacGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, B. A. (1998). Compliance with international agreements. Annual Review of Political Science, 1, 75–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1987). The possibility of cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wit, J. S. (2007). Enhancing U.S. engagement with north Korea. The Washington Quarterly, 30, 53–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamagishi, T. (1986). The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 110–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Akira Okada .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

Proof

The first part of the proposition can be easily seen by the definition of individual rationality. Suppose that a group S of cooperators is Pareto optimal. Then, the largest group N of cooperators is not Pareto superior to S. If S = N, then the condition \(n -\frac{1} {a} \leq s\) trivially holds. If S ≠ N, then a defector outside S is no better off when N is formed than when S is formed. This finding implies that ω + as ω ≥ an ω, that is, \(n -\frac{1} {a} \leq s\). Conversely, suppose that S is not Pareto optimal. Then, there exists some group T ≠ S such that T is Pareto superior to S. Then, there exists some i ∈ T − S. Otherwise, T is never Pareto superior to S according to (6.2). By supposition, it holds that ω + as ω < at ω. Since at ω ≤ an ω, it holds that ω + as ω < an ω, that is, \(n -\frac{1} {a}> s\). This is a contradiction. Q.E.D.

Proposition 6.1 can be generalized to the case that countries have different MPCRs. A group S of cooperators is Pareto optimal if and only if for every T with T − S ≠ ∅ there exists some i ∈ T − S such that \(s \geq t - \frac{1} {a_{i}}\).

Proof

For an individually rational group S, consider the group-trigger strategy such that all members of S cooperate in the first period and keep cooperating as long as all members of S do so (otherwise they contribute nothing forever). All the non-members of S contribute nothing in all periods. The discounted payoff of every member of S for this strategy is thus \(\frac{a_{i}s\omega } {1-\delta }\). If a member defects, then its discounted payoff is at most \(\omega +a_{i}(s - 1)\omega + \frac{\delta } {1-\delta }\omega.\) Thus, the group-trigger strategy for S is a subgame perfect equilibrium of the repeated game G ∞ if \(\frac{a_{i}s\omega } {1-\delta } \geq \omega +a_{i}(s - 1)\omega + \frac{\delta } {1-\delta }\omega\). This condition is equivalent to (6.3). Q.E.D.

Proof

 

  1. (1)

    Suppose that a set of participants S is individually rational. If all participants i ∈ S accept the implementation of S, then they receive the per-period payoff a i s ω. Otherwise, the institution is rejected and thus they receive the per-period payoff ω. Since a i s ω > ω for all i ∈ S, the action profile that all participants accept the implementation of S is a Nash equilibrium of the implementation stage. According to the rule of unanimous voting, the action profiles that at least two participants reject the implementation of S are also Nash equilibria.

  2. (2)

    Suppose that a set of participants S is not individually rational. Then, there exists at least one participant that is strictly better off by rejecting the institution S than when S is implemented. Note that the case of a i s ω = ω is omitted for all i ∈ S since \(\frac{1} {a_{i}}\) is not an integer. Thus, the action profile that all participants accept the implementation of S is not a Nash equilibrium of the implementation stage. Q.E.D.

Proof

If an institution S is implemented in a subgame perfect equilibrium, then S must be individually rational from Proposition 6.1. Conversely, let S be an individually rational group. Consider the following strategy profile. All members of S participate in an institution and no other countries participate. In the implementation stage, S is accepted and all other sets of participants are rejected. It can be shown without much difficulty that this strategy profile induces a Nash equilibrium in the participation stage. For any number of participants s (1 ≤ s ≤ n), consider the strategy profile that all participants reject an institution, regardless of the number of participants. This strategy trivially composes the status-quo equilibrium. Q.E.D.

Proof of Proposition 6.5

According to Proposition 6.3, every individually rational group is accepted to form in a strict subgame perfect equilibrium. Given this equilibrium outcome of the implementation stage, it is sufficient to prove that an action profile of the participation stage is a strict Nash equilibrium if and only if a set of participants S is a critical group. First, suppose that S is a critical group. If any member i of S does not participate in S, then S −{ i} is not individually rational and thus it is not implemented. Country i is worse off by deviating from S and thus the action profile with S is a strict Nash equilibrium. Second, suppose that S is individually rational but not critical. Then, there exists some member i of S that is not critical to S. If country i deviates from S, then it is better off because S −{ i} is individually rational and is implemented. This finding means that the action profile with S is not a Nash equilibrium. Finally, suppose that S is not individually rational. Then, S is not implemented according to Proposition 6.3. Choose any j ∉ S. Country j is better off by joining S if S ∪{ j} is implemented. Otherwise, the per-period payoff of country j does not change. This means that the action profile with S is not a strict Nash equilibrium. Q.E.D.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Japan KK

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Okada, A. (2017). International Cooperation and Institution Formation: A Game Theoretic Perspective. In: Suzuki, M., Okada, A. (eds) Games of Conflict and Cooperation in Asia. The Political Economy of the Asia Pacific. Springer, Tokyo. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-4-431-56466-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation