Reports, Indirect Reports, and Illocutionary Point

  • Chapter
Indirect Reports and Pragmatics

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 5))

Abstract

This essay examines the properties of reports and the diagnostic value of illocutions in reports.

Essentially a report is X’s re-presentation to Y of what Z said. Because X is not identical with Z, what Z said is necessarily transmuted by X. X may use a different medium (e.g. written in place of spoken); X will have a different voice; and X will re-present what Z said, more often than not using different lexis and grammar, even when attempting a verbatim quote. X may have misheard or misinterpreted Z’s utterance: she may add an affective gloss. All of these distinguish X’s report ρ from Z’s utterance υ in both form and content, which renders every report “indirect” to some extent; there are different degrees of indirectness, but a truly indirect report utilises pragmatic enrichment, e.g. when Z’s utterance Its never stopped raining since we arrived is reported as Z complained about the terrible weather there or I won easily is reported as a boast, mistake, or lie.

The accuracy of X’s report ρ depends on whether or not the message in Z’s υ can be reconstructed from it. In other words, the content of ρ is dependent on the content of υ. If υ deviates from the truth in respect of what Z speaks of, then ρ will also deviate from the truth unless X recognizes this deviation and repairs it.

An accurate report ρ re-presents the illocutionary point of the source utterance υ. So a report can function as a diagnostic of the illocutionary point of the source utterance. For instance reports of them show that explicit performative clauses are statements and have truth values. Reports are a means of identifying different functions of imperatives and of disambiguating different utterances of e.g. Out! as a verdictive in a tennis match or a command on some other occasion. And reports help determine whether e.g. ‘whimperatives’ are primarily questions or primarily requests.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 160.49
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 213.99
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 213.99
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    A diary is often treated as an addressee, cf. ‘I don’t want to jot down the facts in this diary the way most people would do, but I want the diary to be my friend, and I’m going to call this friend Kitty.’ (Anne Frank, 1929–1945, Saturday June 20, 1942, Frank, 1997)

  2. 2.

    This is assumed by all those who have sought to explain it, e.g. Davidson (1969), Platts (1979), Cappelen & Lepore (1997), Wieland (2013), among many others.

  3. 3.

    None of Wilson (1959), Quine (1960), nor Davidson (1984) specifically allow for this, but perhaps Dennet (1987) does.

  4. 4.

    This was recognised in Allan (1986b, Vol. 2: 215ff), Allan (1986a), and elsewhere. A similar idea can be found in the work of Alessandro Capone since Capone (2010).

  5. 5.

    Reflexive intention was first recognized by Grice (1957) and has been revised by others, notably Recanati (1987). The speaker has a reflexive intention towards the hearer but not towards an overhearer (Allan, 1986a, 1986b).

  6. 6.

    In a different context Cappelen and Lepore (1997: 280) write: ‘The content of (i.e., the proposition expressed by) an utterance u of a sentence S is p iff It was said that p is a true report of u.’

References

  • Allan, K. (1986a). Hearers, overhearers, and Clark and Carlson’s informative analysis. Language, 62, 509–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allan, K. (1986b). Linguistic meaning (2 Vol.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Reprint ed. Bei**g: World Publishing Corporation, 1991. Reissued in one volume as Routledge Library Editions: Linguistics Vol. 8, 2014.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Allan, K. (1998). Meaning and speech acts. http://users.monash.edu.au/~kallan/papers/Speechacts.html.

  • Allan, K. (2006). Clause-type, primary illocution, and mood-like operators in English. Language Sciences, 28, 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1975). Performatives are statements too. Philosophical Studies 28: 229–236. Reprinted, slightly amended, in Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts (pp. 203–208). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1994a). Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language, 9, 124–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1994b). Semantic slack: What is said and more. In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Foundations of speech act theory: Philosophical and linguistic perspectives (pp. 267–291). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: An experimental and social study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Canegem-Ardijns, I. (2010). The indefeasibility of the inference that if not-A, then not-C. Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). On the social practice of indirect reports (further advances in the study of pragmemes). Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (1997). On an alleged connection between indirect speech and the theory of meaning. Mind & Language, 12, 278–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H., & Carlson, T. B. (1982). Hearers and speech acts. Language, 58, 332–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, LJ. (1964). Do illocutionary forces exist? Philosophical Quarterly, XIV(55), 118–137. Reprinted in Readings in the philosophy of language. J. Rosenberg & C. Travis (Eds.), Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. 1971: 580–599.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1969). On saying that. In D. Davidson & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Words and objections: Essays on the work of W.V. Quine (pp. 158–174). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennet, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, A. M. (1997). The Diary of a Young Girl: The definitive edition. O. Frank & M. Pressler (Eds.), (Transl: Susan Massotty). London: Puffin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geis, M., & Zwicky, A. (1971). On invited inferences. Linguistic Inquiry, 2, 561–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of talk. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66: 377–388. Reprinted in Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words (pp. 213–223). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355). Dordrecht: Reidel. Republished separately as Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell. (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, A. (1989). Remembering and representing prose: quoted speech as a data source. Discourse Processes, 12, 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese 22: 18–67. Reprinted in Semantics of natural language (pp. 169–218). D. Donald & H. Gilbert (Eds.), Dordrecht: Reidel. 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation (Vol. 2 Vol.). London: John W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oxford English Dictionary. (1989). (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Abbreviated to OED]. Also available on Compact Disc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platts, M. (1979). Ways of meaning: An introduction to a philosophy of language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1987). Meaning and force: The pragmatics of performative utterances. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2001). Open quotation. Mind, 110, 637–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, J. M. (1974). Toward a linguistic theory of speech acts. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, J. M. (1970). Whimperatives. In J. M. Sadock & A. L. Vanek (Eds.), Studies presented to Robert B. Lees by his students (pp. 223–238). Linguistic Research Institute: Edmonton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, P. (2011). Quotation and conceptions of language. Dialectica, 65, 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1995). Relevance: Communication and cognition (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell [First ed. 1986].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, N. (2013). Indirect reports and pragmatics. In C. Alessandro, P. Franco Lo, & C. Marco (Eds.), Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy (pp. 389–411). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, N. L. (1959). Substances without substrata. The Review of Metaphysics, 12, 521–539.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Keith Allan .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Allan, K. (2016). Reports, Indirect Reports, and Illocutionary Point. In: Capone, A., Kiefer, F., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Indirect Reports and Pragmatics. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21395-8_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21395-8_27

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-21394-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-21395-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation