Implying, Precluding, and Quantifying Over: Frege’s Logical Expressivism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Priority of Propositions. A Pragmatist Philosophy of Logic

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 475))

Abstract

There are 16 bivalent binary truth functions, but only two fundamental logical relations between propositions: implying and precluding. In addition, some higher-level concepts express the scope and nature of inferential relations. In this chapter, I will explain Frege’s treatment of these two notions, which are the semantic and pragmatic support for conditionality and negation. I will also offer an explanation of Frege’s semantic account of universal and existential quantifiers, and the relations between them. The richness and originality of Frege’s semantics manifest in his treatment of the role of logical notions and related expressions. Frege’s logic is nothing more (and nothing less) than his semantics for logical terms together with an appropriate method for representing inferential transitions. The deductive system that converts a language into a calculus is the representation of the commitments and entitlements that individuate concepts and propositional contents. The very notation that Frege introduces shows that logical notions do not affect judgeable contents, which systematically occur as arguments of the former. In this chapter, I will argue that Frege defended an expressivist approach to the meaning of logical notions. Frege’s insights at this point can help in the as-yet unfinished task of giving a satisfactory semantics for logical notions. I consider Frege’s views and suggestions entirely correct.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 96.29
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As I will explain in the next section, Begriffsschrift explains the meaning of the conditional stroke (§5) and negation (§7) on expressivist lines. Some of Frege’s Logical Investigations, where he deals with generality (Frege, 1923) and negation (Frege, 1918–9b), also suggest this expressivist approach.

  2. 2.

    In the Begriffsschrift, §5. One might retort at this point that the conditional and implication are different notions. In one case, the relation between the two propositions involved is contingent, and in the other it is necessary. This point will be discussed in the Chap. 6. But here it suffices to say that conditional terms (‘if’, ‘when’) are natural language tools for expressing implication (in a broad sense).

  3. 3.

    For an up-to-date survey, see e.g. (Stanley & Szabó, 2003).

References

  • Ammereller, E., & Fischer, E. (2004). Wittgenstein at work. Method in the philosophical investigations. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. Victor Gollanz Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4(2), 159–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2015). A modality called ‘negation’. Mind, 124(495), 761–793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besson, C. (2019). Logical expressivism and Carroll’s regress. In M. J. Frápolli (Ed.), Expressivisms, knowledge and truth (Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 86) (pp. 35–62). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, D. (1987). Semantic constraints on relevance. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons. An introduction to inferentialism. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2014). Analytic pragmatism, expressivism, and modality. The 2014 Nordic pragmatism lectures. www.nordprag.org

  • Brandom, R. (2019). A spirit of trust. A reading of Hege’s phenomenology. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1932). The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language. Erkenntnis, 60–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege (Philosophy of language). Haper and Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (2012). ¿Qué son las constantes lógicas? Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, 44(132), 65–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (2019). Propositions first. Biting Geachs bullet. In Expressivisms, knowledge and truth. Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement 86. Edited by María J. Frápolli. Cambridge University Press, 87–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, a formula language, modeled upon that of arithmetic, for pure thought. In Jean van Heijenoort (1967). From Frege to Gödel. A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, 1–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1880–1). Booles logical Calculus and the Concept-script. In G. Frege (1979), Posthumous writings. Edited by Hans Hermes, Friedrich Kambarte, Friedrich Kaulbach. Basil Blackwell, 9–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). The Foundations of Arithmetic. A logic-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. Translated by J. L. Austin. Second Revised Edition. New York, Harper Torchbooks / The Science Library, Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1891). Function and Concept. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 137–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892a). Concept and Object. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Basil Blackwell, 182–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892b). On Sense and Meaning. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Basil Blackwell, 157–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1893–1903/2013). Basic laws of arithmetic. Volumes I and II. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1897). On Mr. Peano’s conceptual notation and my own. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Basil Blackwell, 234–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1918–19b). Negation. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Basil Blackwell, 373–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1923). Logical generality. In G. Frege (1979), Posthumous writings. Edited by Hans Hermes, Friedrich Kambarte, Friedrich Kaulbach. Basil Blackwell, 258–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1923–26). Compound thoughts. In G. Frege (1984), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Edited by Brian McGuinness. Basil Blackwell, 390–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1960). Ascriptivism. The Philosophical Review, 69(2), 221–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1997). No scope for scope? Linguistics and Philosophy, 20(5), 515–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2015a). Proof-theoretic semantics, a problem with negation and prospects for modality. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(6), 713–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2015b). What is wrong with classical negation? Grazer Philosophische Studien, 92(1), 51–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2019). Proof and falsity: A logical Investigation. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lindström, P. (1966). First order predicate logic with generalized quantifiers. Theoria, 32(3), 186–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macbeth, D. (2005). Frege’s logic. Harvard University Press (kindle edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In P. Suppes, J. Moravcsik, & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 221–242).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mostowski, A. (1957). On a generalization of quantifiers. Fundamenta Mathematica, 44, 12–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odgen, C. K., & Richards, I. A. (1923). The meaning of meaning. Harcourt Brace & Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1935/2002). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. (2006). Meaning approached via proofs. Synthese, 148, 507–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffrin, D. (1986). Functions of and in discourse. Journal of Pragmatics, 10, 41–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffrin, D. (1987). Discourse markers. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schröder, E. (1880). Gottlob Frege, Begriffsschrift. Zeitschrift für Mathematik und Physik, 25, 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sluga, H. (1987). Frege against the Boleans. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 28(1), 80–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2003). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind and Language, 15, 219–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, C. (1937). The emotive meaning of ethical terms. Mind, 46, 14–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1914/1998). Notebooks 1914–1916. Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frápolli, M.J. (2023). Implying, Precluding, and Quantifying Over: Frege’s Logical Expressivism. In: The Priority of Propositions. A Pragmatist Philosophy of Logic. Synthese Library, vol 475. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-25229-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation