Exploring the No-Show Paradox for Condorcet Extensions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Evaluating Voting Systems with Probability Models

Part of the book series: Studies in Choice and Welfare ((WELFARE))

Abstract

An important and surprising phenomenon in voting theory is the No-Show Paradox (NSP), which occurs if a voter is better off by abstaining from an election. While it is known that certain voting rules suffer from this paradox in principle, the extent to which it is of practical concern is not well understood. We aim at filling this gap by analyzing the likelihood of the NSP for six Condorcet extensions (Black’s rule, Baldwin’s rule, Nanson’s rule, Max-Min, Tideman’s rule, and Copeland’s rule) under various preference models using Ehrhart theory as well as extensive computer simulations. We find that, for few alternatives, the probability of the NSP is rather small (less than 4% for four alternatives and all considered preference models, except for Copeland’s rule). As the number of alternatives increases, the NSP becomes much more likely and which rule is most susceptible to abstention strongly depends on the underlying distribution of preferences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
EUR 128.39
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
EUR 171.19
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
EUR 171.19
Price includes VAT (Germany)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free ship** worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Interestingly, when considering set-valued or probabilistic voting rules, there are Condorcet extensions immune to the NSP  under suitable assumptions (Brandl et al. 2019a, b).

  2. 2.

    Note that other discriminating Condorcet extensions such as Kemeny’s rule, Dodgson’s rule, and Young’s rule are NP-hard to compute see, e.g., Brandl et al. (2016a).

  3. 3.

    Tideman’s rule is arguably the least well-known voting rule presented here. It was proposed to efficiently approximate Dodgson’s rule and is not to be confused with ranked pairs which is sometimes also called Tideman’s rule. Also note that the ‘dual’ rule returning alternatives for which the sum of weighted pairwise majority wins is maximal is not a Condorcet extension.

  4. 4.

    For both MaxiMin and Tideman’s rule, this holds by the observation that a weak Condorcet winner does not lose any pairwise majority comparison. Black’s rule fails to be a weak Condorcet extension by definition; a counterexample for Baldwin’s, Nanson’s, and Copeland’s rule is given by Fishburn (1977).

  5. 5.

    More precisely, \(P_n\) is a dilated polytope depending on n, \({P_n = nP = \{n\mathbf {x}:\mathbf {x}\in P\}}\).

  6. 6.

    Theoretically, we only require \(g_{ad}-1 \le g_{bc} \le g_{ad}\). As either all \(g_{xy}\) are even or all \(g_{xy}\) are odd, this collapses to \(g_{ad} = g_{bc}\).

  7. 7.

    Some inequalities are omitted to remove redundancies when taken together with later constraints.

  8. 8.

    We choose this informal notation for the sake of readability. It is to be understood in a way that \(P_1\) is the polytope described by (in)equalities labelled (basis) as well as (A). We additionally assume for all polytopes that the sum of voters per type adds up to n and each type consists of a nonnegative number of voters.

  9. 9.

    This effect is only relevant when there are at least four alternatives.

  10. 10.

    For Black’s rule, we find that the polynomial would be of period \(q \approx 2.7\times 10^7\) corresponding to a mid two-digit GB file size.

  11. 11.

    Felsenthal and Nurmi (2018) also show that none of the two rules fares strictly better than the other. Indeed, there are profiles where a manipulation is possible according to Baldwin’s rule but not using Nanson’s rule and vice versa.

  12. 12.

    For Black’s rule, manipulation is only possible either towards or away from a Condorcet winner since Borda’s rule is immune to strategic abstention and manipulation is impossible from Condorcet winner to Condorcet winner.

  13. 13.

    For increasing m the computations quickly become very demanding. The values for \({m=30}\) and \({n\ge 99}\) are determined with 50 000 runs each only. The size of all 95% confidence intervals is, however, still within \(0.5\%\).

  14. 14.

    For instance the profile allowing for a manipulation under Copeland’s rule is immune to the NSP for all other rules. It features 10 alternatives and 30 voters. Baldwin’s and Nanson’s rule exhibit the NSP for the same profile.

References

  • Baldwin JM (1926) The technique of the Nanson preferential majority system of election. Tran Proc R Soc Victoria 39:42–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg S (1985) Paradox of voting under an urn model: the effect of homogeneity. Publ Choice 47:377–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black D (1958) The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandl F, Brandt F, Hofbauer J (2015) Incentives for participation and abstention in probabilistic social choice. In: Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS). IFAAMAS, pp 1411–1419

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandl F, Brandt F, Hofbauer J (2017) Random assignment with optional participation. In: Proceedings of the 16th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS). IFAAMAS, pp 326–334

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandl F, Brandt F, Geist C, Hofbauer J (2019) Strategic abstention based on preference extensions: positive results and computer-generated impossibilities. J Artif Intel Res 66:1031–1056

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandl F, Brandt F, Hofbauer J (2019b) Welfare maximization entices participation. Games Econ Behav 14:308–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Conitzer V, Endriss U, Lang J, Procaccia A (eds) (2016) Handbook of computational social choice. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Geist C, Strobel M (2016) Analyzing the practical relevance of voting paradoxes via Ehrhart theory, computer simulations, and empirical data. In: Proceedings of the 15th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (AAMAS). IFAAMAS, pp 385–393

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Geist C, Peters D (2017) Optimal bounds for the no-show paradox via SAT solving. Math Social Sci 90:18–27 (special Issue in Honor of Hervé Moulin)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruns W, Söger C (2015) The computation of generalized Ehrhart series in Normaliz. J Symb. Comput. 68(2):75–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruns W, Ichim B, Römer T, Sieg R, Söger C (2019) Normaliz. Algorithms for rational cones and affine monoids. https://www.normaliz.uni-osnabrueck.de

  • Bruns W, Ichim B, Söger C (2019b) Computations of volumes and Ehrhart series in four candidates elections. Annals Oper Res 280(1–2):241–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland AH (1951) A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function. Mimeo, University of Michigan Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchlow DE, Fligner MA, Verducci JS (1991) Probability models on rankings. J Math Psychol 35:294–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Loera JA, Hemmecke R, Tauzer J, Yoshida R (2004) Effective lattice point counting in rational convex polytopes. J Symb Comput 38(4):1273–1302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Loera JA, Dutra B, Köppe M, Moreinis S, Pinto G, Wu J (2012) Software for exact integration of polynomials over polyhedra. ACM Commun Comput Algebra 45(3/4):169–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Duddy C (2014) Condorcet’s principle and the strong no-show paradoxes. Theory Decis 77(2):275–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrhart E (1962) Sur les polyèdres rationnels homothétiques à \(n\) dimensions. Compte-Rendus de l’académie des Sciences 254(4):616–618

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal DS, Nurmi H (2018) Monotonicity violations by Borda’s elimination and Nanson’s rules: a comparison. Group Decis Negot 27(4):637–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33(3):469–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC, Brams SJ (1983) Paradoxes of preferential voting. Math Mag 56(4):207–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV, Fishburn PC (1976) Concorcet’s paradox and anonymous preference profiles. Publ Choice 26(1):1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV, Lepelley D (2011) Voting paradoxes and group coherence. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV, Lepelley D (2017) Elections. Studies in choice and welfare. Voting rules and paradoxical outcomes. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Jimeno JL, Pérez J, García E (2009) An extension of the Moulin no show paradox for voting correspondences. Social Choice Welf 33(3):343–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa E, Merlin V, Top FM (2018) Scoring run-off rules, single-peaked preferences and paradoxes of variable electorate. Working paper

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer GH (1977) A dynamical model of political equilibrium. J Econ Theory 16(2):310–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Breton M, Lepelley D, Smaoui H (2016) Correlation, partitioning and the probability of casting a decisive vote under the majority rule. J Math Econ 64:11–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley D, Merlin V (2000) Scoring run-off paradoxes for variable electorates. Econ Theory 17(1):53–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley D, Chantreuil F, Berg S (1996) The likelihood of monotonicity paradoxes in run-off elections. Math Social Sci 31(3):133–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley D, Louichi A, Smaoui H (2008) On Ehrhart polynomials and probability calculations in voting theory. Social Choice Welf 30(3):363–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley D, Moyouwou I, Smaoui H (2018) Monotonicity paradoxes in three-candidate elections using scoring elimination rules. Social Choice Welf 50(1):1–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallows CL (1957) Non-null ranking models. Biometrika 44(1/2):114–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marden JI (1995) Analyzing and modeling rank data. In: Monographs on statistics and applied probability, vol 64. Chapman & Hall

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattei N, Walsh T (2013) PrefLib: a library for preference data. In: Proceedings of the 3rd International Conference on Algorithmic Decision Theory (ADT). Lecture Notes in Computer Science (LNCS), vol 8176, Springer, pp 259–270

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1988) Condorcet’s principle implies the no show paradox. J Econ Theory 45(1):53–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanson EJ (1883) Methods of election. Trans Proc R Soc Victoria 19:197–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Niou EMS (1987) A note on Nanson’s rule. Publ Choice 54:191–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez J (2001) The strong no show paradoxes are a common flaw in condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice Welf 18(3):601–616

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez J, Jimeno JL, García E (2010) No show paradox in condorcet k-voting procedure. Group Decis Negot 21(3):291–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez J, Jimeno JL, García E (2015) No show paradox and the golden number in generalized Condorcet voting methods. Group Decis Negot 24:497–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plassmann F, Tideman N (2014) How frequently do different voting rules encounter voting paradoxes in three-candidate elections? Social Choice Welf 42(1):31–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ray D (1986) On the practical possibility of a ‘no show paradox’ under the single transferable vote. Math Social Sci 11(2):183–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter M, Grofman B, Marley AAJ, Tsetlin IM (2006) Behavioral social choice: probabilistic models, statistical inference, and applications. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Schürmann A (2013) Exploiting polyhedral symmetries in social choice. Social Choice Welf 40(4):1097–1110

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson P (1969) On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Quart J Econ 83(3):478–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tideman TN (1987) Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice Welf 4(3):185–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsetlin I, Regenwetter M, Grofman B (2003) The impartial culture maximizes the probability of majority cycles. Social Choice Welf 21(3):387–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson MC, Pritchard G (2007) Probability calculations under the IAC hypothesis. Math Social Sci 54(3):244–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Preliminary results of this chapter were presented at the 14th Meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare (Seoul, June 2018), the 7th International Workshop on Computational Social Choice (Troy, June 2018), the AAMAS-IJCAI Workshop on Agents and Incentives in Artificial Intelligence (Stockholm, July 2018), and the 18th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (Montréal, May 2019).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felix Brandt .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Brandt, F., Hofbauer, J., Strobel, M. (2021). Exploring the No-Show Paradox for Condorcet Extensions. In: Diss, M., Merlin, V. (eds) Evaluating Voting Systems with Probability Models. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-48598-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Navigation